Quantcast
Channel: sexuality – The Semipermeable Membrane
Viewing all 19 articles
Browse latest View live

Research Paper: Sex and Stats

$
0
0

One of the courses I am attending this year is a research seminar on Cold War science. I am not sure how to phrase this—”despite” or “even though”—, but as a student in Germany, I had no idea what impact the Cold War had on natural and social sciences, and how deeply intertwined modern genetics and the atomic bomb are, for example. These Tuesday classes are definitely my least enjoyable regarding subject matter, because I simply cannot deal unemotionally with human experiments, hydrogen bombs, and non-heterosexuals driven into suicide. Yet, it is one of my (three) favorite classes; since not only what I learn concerning methodology and content, but also my excitement for my own research project within the course exceed my expectations.

After realizing that John W. Tukey did not only work on missiles, the Census, and ozone depletion, but was also member of the methodological review committee of Alfred C. Kinsey’s report on male sexuality, I went to the American Philosophical Society Archives to have a look at some of the Tukey papers. The collection is huge, but I found some interesting issues around which I framed the research proposal to my professor:

I want to explore the Cold War connection of Alfred C. Kinsey et al.’s sex research shortly after World War II, or rather the effort that was put into assessing and improving the validity of its data analysis and conclusions (1950–1952).—Kinsey and his co-workers published a report on Sexual Behavior in the Human Male in 1948, having been financially supported by the National Research Council’s (NRC’s) Committee for Research in Problems of Sex (CRPS), which continued funding Kinsey’s further studies on female sexuality through the 1950s. After publishing the Kinsey Report, however, the research group was widely criticized for its data acquisition and interpretation methods. Thus, the NRC requested the American Statistical Association (ASA) to appoint a committee for estimating the validity of the Kinsey Report. Three statisticians were designated members of the committee, one of them John W. Tukey. In cooperation with Kinsey’s research group at the University of Indiana, Bloomington, the committee reviewed the statistical methods of the Kinsey Report, and claimed to focus entirely on the validity of data interpretation, i.e., to exclude the matter of male sexuality and orgasm from their inquiry—a fact which may reflect the reviewers’ lacking experience in the human sciences. Being notably rushed by the CRPS due to newspaper speculations on the reasons for a methodological Kinsey Report review, the report was completed in 1952, and published in the ASA journal in the following year.1

Besides Tukey’s papers, which include subject files on the Kinsey Report evaluation and correspondence with the ASA, the American Philosophical Society (APS) holds papers on Frederick Mosteller’s work on the Kinsey Report—Mosteller was another review committee member (circa two linear feet). Not only correspondence amongst the committee members, between the committee and Kinsey, as well as between the committee and the ASA, but also annotated drafts of the review report, and a collection of published criticisms on the Kinsey Report can be found in the collections. If time allows, I could also visit the National Academy of Science’s archives, where the records of the CRPS are held (1920–1965). Among other papers, the collection comprises ten feet of records about persons and institutions the CRPS worked with, and about sexuality research support in specific, including grant applications.

In exploiting these sources, I hope to be able to profile the work of the review committee on the Kinsey Report, and to gain understanding in statistical work during an early stage of the Cold War. I want to learn more about the review committee’s appointment: Who decided to request such a committee and for which purpose? Who chose its members? What kind of negotiations between the CRPS, the ASA, the review committee, and the research group around Kinsey took place before and after the committee had commenced its work? What outcome of the review was anticipated by the respective agents? If possible, I want to extend my investigation on the NRC CRPS in order to learn more about if and by what means this NRC Committee influenced sexuality research and its perception through financial support; but also in what way evaluation of funded research influenced its direction. Moreover, it seems worth an attempt to find out which scientific, political and social developments led to the CRPS’s discharge in 1963.

Not much neuroscience there, but a lot of brain … The revised and extended five-page version of the proposal is due tomorrow, so I better get started right away. And I have not forgotten that I wanted to share some more thoughts on stats, besides these Tukey-connected ones. Mary Morgan and her pretty white-dotted red cardigan are still on my mind.

1 William G. Cochran / Frederick Mosteller / John W. Tukey (1952): “Statistical Problems of the Kinsey Report.” In Journal of the American Statistical Association 48, pp. 673–716.


“A very Unusual Person”

$
0
0

I do not read horoscopes, but I love personality tests. I admit that this is weird, because one makes promises (nearly?) as false as the other, but I find the attempt of measuring human character and abilities in numbers marvelously interesting. Finally, with my project on the methodological review of the Kinsey Report, I have a respectable reason for taking some of these tests during my work time—and learn about my sexual orientation.

One of Kinsey et al.’s findings was that sexual orientation is not dichotomic. Instead, they proposed a scale on which they measured sexuality between the poles “Exclusively Heterosexual” (0) and “Exclusively Homosexual” (6).1 Similar to “What Kind of Bride Are You?,” this scale offers several categories of which one should pretty likely cover your preferences. The first test I took several months ago, was in German, pretty short and boring. Four questions, and the answer was not even phrased in Kinsey’s terms. Even my grandmother could have given me that kind of diagnosis. The second one I liked much better: Questions 7 to 11 are hilarious, and I cannot deprive you of them. Since the test is also in German, I will translate them for you:

7) Did you sometimes get nervous when an attractive female or male (!) hairdresser … touched you?
8) Did you feel comfortable with their touching you?
9) Did it make you nervous?
10) Did you enjoy their touching you?
11) Did you wish by yourself that they would go on touching you?

So, please imagine yourself going to an expensive hairdresser.2 It is cold outside, but they wash your hair with warm water and give you this massage of which you wish it might never end. Of course I am comfortable with that! Of course the thought this situation might be over in a few minutes makes me nervous! Of course I enjoy it! Of course I wish they would go on and on and … What a ridiculous set of questions to determine my sexual preferences.

The most interesting one in English I found so far, does not ask for your feelings when touched by a hairdresser. What makes it so special, is that after answering some questions which are obviously related to your sexuality, you are redirected to another page where you have to answer some seemingly random questions concerning hobbies, ethnicity, etc. Only after answering these, you get access to your Kinsey grade. I was totally blown away when I realized that I just witnessed an instance of profiling humans with regard to bodily and behavioral features. As if that were not enough, the Kinsey grade I had worked so hard for could not be determined! I am obviously a “very unusual person,” and therefore they were not able to match me to one of Kinsey’s groups. (It worked for several friends of mine; so there is either a bug that does only affect those with the most honorable intentions, or my way of answering the questions is indeed very uncommon and requires such a result.) My reaction was quite ambiguous: One part of me crowed over this test’s inability to put parts of my personality in numbers, but the other one was seriously offended by the stupid machine’s assertion that I am either too dumb to click “True” or “False,” or “very unusual,” which to me sounded like “interesting,” “special,” or “nice” as euphemism for … you know.

Screenshot 10/15/2013 (Tabea Cornel, CC BY-NC-SA 2.0)

Screenshot 10/15/2013 (Tabea Cornel, CC BY-NC-SA 2.0)

Needless to say that none of the tests came to the same conclusion about my sexual preferences. I find it much more interesting that this system of putting people’s personalities in numbers is directly linked with the advertisement industry, a worldwide system of profiling people. I am wondering what Kinsey would have said if somebody had told him about that before he died. Not only this use of his system, but also the way the data is acquired (anonymous, using a standardized questionnaire with binary answering options) might have troubled him. Kinsey interviewed people personally before he drew conclusions about their sexual life, and he spent years finding trustworthy and skilled assistants to carry out this task. I am curios to learn about the processes that allowed de-personalizing his system to a rigid online test, and re-personalizing as well as enriching the data again as part of a capitalist consumer surveillance system.

Do you see how the list of investigational categories is growing? We have sexuality, we have handedness, and we have sex/gender. Add intelligence, age, education, etc., and imagine how the advertising industry would thank us if we made these numbers about us available to them—and told them afterwards how many hours we run per week. Somebody has to come up with a possibility to unite all these scattered tests to a comprehensive one. The Big Siblings will love it.

1 On what this meant during the early Cold War era, I highly recommend David K. Johnson’s The Lavender Scare.

2 I suggest you go to Sassoon in Berlin (ask for Peter, but note that he is only there on Saturdays, since he decided to go to school again), or Haartrend Reichardt in Speyer (tell Willi I said hi).

Impressive Brains: Latour and Bechdel, Cartoons and ANT

$
0
0

“I am not a closed circuit; I don’t trust my own subjectivity. This is why I try to get as much outside-assertion as I can.”—It’s almost a month ago since Alison Bechdel stated this confession during her keynote address for the Queer Method Conference at Penn on October 31st. I suggest you find a way to get to know her work, listen to her, and see her (!). But try not to freak out during Q&A and tell her how much you admire her, or she will ask you to “please, keep cool.” Afterwards, I suggest you go home and read Latour’s Reassembling the Social.

Not only that Latour obviously likes cartoons (Fig. 1) and other vivid illustrations of his concepts (a classmate of mine made a list containing dozens of his hilarious analogies; I will ask him for an electronic copy, and try to post it here), he seems to respond to some of Bechdel’s uncertainties concerning subjectivity. Since he promises to revalue objectivity (124 f.), subjectivity as opposed to objectivity loses relevance. In transforming the concept of objectivity, Latour offers Bechdel a tool to write about herself in a “warm, interested, controversial” way (125) without making use of her untrustworthy subjectivity: His concept of objectivity as “the presence of many objectors” (ibid.) could grant Bechdel a new perspectivity avoiding her supposedly treacherous subjectivity.

Bechdel already employs “relativity” (146) as suggested by Latour: In knowing her limited view of the world, she prepares her sketches by photographing herself in different poses—or “standpoints” (ibid.). These changes of perspective allow her to reveal and create more and more ties between objects, objectors, and objections. Latour’s view of ANT as method for generating complex accounts (138) is also well in line with Bechdel’s agenda: Her practice in drawing and shading is literally multi-layering (cf. 144), and her attempt to imitate Charles Joseph Minard’s skillfulness in creating a graph of her mother’s life illustrates her belief in the importance of displaying multi-dimensionally entangled relations.

Bechdel’s amazing method of researching and historicizing can serve as an intriguing exemplar for dealing with ghosts a historian of science might discover in the archives, for how to bring them back to life, give them a voice, do “history from the inside out,”1 and yet be aware of the modifying power of my own interpretation. Besides, giving such a painstaking account of real people is one of Latour’s complexity “tests” for “good ANT account[s]” (30). They are particularly interesting in juxtaposition to his appreciation for standards and metrology. According to ANT, successful “description[s]” (147) should be at least as “interesting” (30), fidgety (128 f.; 138), and complex (138) as what they portray.

Latour’s requirement might sound rather puzzling at first, since a model as detailed as the original is certainly of little value—we could as well build globes with a 12,715.43 km diameter (still not willing to let go of the metric system, sorry). Moreover, Latour’s conviction that standards are inevitable features of “being human” (230) does not seem to harmonize with his demand for complexity, at least not at first glance. It appears to me that he draws a line between standardizing practice on the one hand, and the non-structuralist assessment of a society acting this way on the other hand (cf. 153). Ties and agency in the realms of scientific activity can certainly be traced very well if one follows these travelling “universals” (229); they are necessary and enabling for science itself, and fruitful starting points for ANT analyses.

How does this relate to my own project?—I like the idea of challenging neuroscientists with the request for a more complex model of the brain, for a less reductionist way of thinking and researching. Still, precisely the standards they set offer me a starting point for my analyses, helping to uncover how and where these scientists build landings on which they can rest, find a common basis for arguing, hopefully also re-orienting themselves, and deciding on further steps. Standards of this sort can be social agreements, collective vocabularies, accepted methods, common beliefs, shared technologies, and many more. Unlike Bechdel, however, I do not want to uncover my own history; therefore, I should avoid posing on these landings in order to prevent drawing sketches of myself modelling for the researchers I am trying to display. The history I want to write should much more be inspired by looking the archival ghosts or active researchers over their shoulders, using the glasses they wear.

That is certainly not easy to achieve, but luckily, Latour offers quite some helpful suggestions for writing a good social history of science: Do not attempt to uncover causalities, reasons, or the motive in actions; instead, only try to formulate influencing factors (52); know the science before you start writing about it (57); do not succumb to the belief that science is singled out of other human activities (101); if you are able to deal with “shifting ontologies,” you chose the right field to become a pioneer pretty easily (119); do not try to imitate a scientific style in your writing (125); do not abuse your actors as string puppets to found your claim or hide your lack of insight (130); go for source-based case studies and leave your frames on the wall (143)—and don’t be too creative, “[d]on’t fill it in” (150). I hope this last suggestion is not directed against Alison Bechdel. If you watched the videos, you should realize that she did a pretty good job.

1 Only one of David Barnes‘ great advices.

Quick Updates on Sex/Stats and Latour

$
0
0

As I promised before I got almost entirely caught up in working hard on my final assignments, I asked Kevin Gotkin to pass along the Latour analogy sheet he compiled for our class. Download it here, and enjoy!

Besides, I wanted to share the abstract of the Tukey/Kinsey paper I am currently working on. I shared my research proposal with you earlier. I will not post the whole thing, because I intend to make this a publishable article. Thus, this is only meant to stimulate your thoughts, and maybe you would like to share them (comment or email!).

During the years 1950–1952, John W. Tukey served on a review committee to assess Alfred C. Kinsey’s sex research on methodological terms. He and two other statisticians agreed to exclude all non-technical and non-expositional matters from their review. Drawing mostly on their correspondence within these two years, this paper traces the political and personal threads which made it impossible for the evaluators to live up to this claim. Against the background of sexuality as highly contested category during the McCarthy era, negotiations with Kinsey and his funding institutions became an important part of the review group’s work. Upholding the view that sound data and proper methods could produce objective validity required a virtual enclosure of the statistical review group: Their internal communication differed widely from the published appraisal; Tukey was the most ambiguous and dynamic character in this connection. This incidence sheds light on an early stage of Tukey’s career, which later led him to become an influential contributor to Cold War science and policy.

M.A. Thesis: Functional Magnetic Resonance Phrenology?

$
0
0

In the process of revising a paper on F.J. Gall’s conception of sex/gender and the status of sexuality in his so-called organological doctrine, I reread two German articles by Frank Stahnisch (who is a great scholar and an incredibly helpful person): “Über die Natur des weiblichen Gehirns” and “Über die neuronale Natur des Weiblichen.”1 I was reminded how beautiful it is to read—and write—German texts.2 Apart from very few long emails, the last substantial thing I have written in the tongue of the umlauts is my M.A. thesis. I won’t publish it, but it seems a shame not to make it accessible. I included an English description of its argument in my very first blog post.

Download the .pdf here; I had to omit the illustrations due to copyright issues, but they aren’t crucial for my argument in any sense. Have fun!

1 More publications of his in German and English are available through the University of Calgary.
2 In case you want you read a fabulous account on what it feels like to write in a second language and trying to find a new home in it, check out this article my friend Tamar Novick shared with me (thank you again, Tamar!).

Upcoming Talk in Lisbon in September

$
0
0

The program for the ESHS Annual Meeting in Lisbon, September 4–6, is online now. I will be presenting my research on the morning of the third conference day, session 58 I (Saturday, September 6, 9.00–11.00 am). Here is the abstract I proposed:

Contested Numbers: The Quest for Objective Validity in a Statistical Review of the “Kinsey Report”

The media response to A.C. Kinsey et al.’s Sexual Behavior in the Human Male (1948) was massive and controversial. Kinsey’s funding institutions—the Rockefeller Foundation and the National Research Council’s Committee for Research in Problems of Sex—were particularly concerned about methodological criticisms and requested the American Statistical Association to assess the validity of Kinsey’s results.
During the years 1950–1952, World War II companions and mathematicians William C. Cochran, C. Frederick Mosteller and John W. Tukey served on this review committee. Drawing mostly on Tukey’s papers and the review group’s internal correspondence during the collaboration, this project traces the political and personal threads which made it impossible for the evaluators to live up to their initial claim that they would exclude all non-technical and non-expositional matters from their review.
Sexuality was a highly contested category during the McCarthy era. Diverse personal interests as well as concerns about political and public response further complicated communication between the review committee on the one hand, and Kinsey’s research group as well as his funding institutions on the other hand. As a result, continuous negotiations of partiality and diplomacy became an important part of the statisticians’ work. Upholding the view that sound data and proper methods could produce objective validity required a virtual enclosure of the review group: They developed statistical methods that they knew would never be used by Kinsey’s team, and formulated a devastating secret evaluation of Kinsey’s methods. The informal and sarcastic tone of their internal communication differed widely from the correspondence with Kinsey himself and his funding institutions on the one hand, and from the mild and appreciative published appraisal on the other hand. This incident sheds light on how scientists navigated their interests and (mis)communicated their true results in an early stage of the Cold War imbroglio.

In May, I was provided with incredible 90 minutes to present and discuss the same research project at the History of Science research colloquium at TU Berlin, thanks to the invitation of my M.A. thesis advisor Friedrich Steinle. It was a fun evening, especially because I gave the talk in English, but Q&A was bilingual. It was challenging to switch languages quickly, in particular because I had worked on this exclusively in English—and I wouldn’t have thought that I could lose familiarity with my own mother tongue so quickly. Anyway, please join me in Lisbon in September!

(Fun fact: except for Clara Kinsey, only men appear as the pursuers and objects of the research I will be talking about; yet, I will be joining the session on “Women and Science in Focus.”)

Help Needed for Survey of (Natural/Medical/Social) Scientists

$
0
0

Today I want to ask you to contribute your perspective on sex/gender and other types of classification of human subjects in your research on behalf of my Berlinian colleague Diana Schellenberg (psychologist). Please find her call for participants for her study below. (And PLEASE take the time to support her research, since it’s very important from a meta-science point of view; besides that, she asked me to post this announcement on my weblog, so it’s also about my being able to motivate readers to participate—reimbursement with chocolate and gratitude is guaranteed if you let me know that you completed the survey.)

Dear Tabea,

As you may recall, I am writing my dissertation on sex/gender in empirical research. Part of the thesis is concerned with the views and methods that medical, psychological and neuroscientific researchers employ when conceptualizing and operationalizing sex/gender in their studies. I am currently conducting an online survey to obtain as many perspectives as possible from researchers of various backgrounds and from all over the world.

I would greatly appreciate your input and would like to cordially invite you to participate in the 45- to 60-minute survey that can be spread out over several sessions. I would also greatly appreciate if you were to recommend the survey to your colleagues.

Please be assured that, although I personalized this e-mail, the survey is anonymous and involves many participants, so I will not know who follows the link below and participates in the study.

You can find the survey here.

If you would like some additional information, please find it in the recruitment letter below this e-mail and feel free to contact me at any time.

 

SEEKING RESEARCHERS FOR ONLINE SURVEY ON SEX/GENDER IN EMPIRICAL RESEARCH

My PhD thesis1 is concerned with sex/gender assessment in empirical research. In a first step, I would like to learn about researchers’ sex/gender-related perspectives and methods.

I am inviting empirical researchers
- from the natural, social and life sciences (e.g. medicine, psychology, neuroscience, biology, sociology and related fields)
- who conduct research with human participants, in which participant sex/gender has ever played any role (e.g., related to equipment, sample descriptions, research questions, and/or any type of data analysis)
- from anywhere in the world
to take part in a survey that
- takes about 45-60 minutes to complete (several short sessions possible)
- can be paused and returned to via personalized hyperlink
- will be analyzed descriptively (no attempts to draw causal conclusions from your answers).

Sex/gender does not have to be your research focus. Even if sex/gender plays a minor role in your research (e.g., you solely use it to describe your sample), your participation is extremely valuable.

The project is intended to be as transparent as possible, and I am interested in your honest opinions and methods regarding sex/gender in your research, so please be assured that the survey is anonymous and does not contain any deceptive or experimental elements. A similar survey will be conducted with persons, who are likely to be in the role of research participants (“potential study participants”).

If you would like to participate in the survey, please follow this link.

If you have any questions, feel free to contact me at dischellenberg@mailbox.tu-berlin.de.

Thank you for your time and support.

Best regards,
Diana Schellenberg, Dipl.-Psych.
Department of Educational Psychology
Technische Universität Berlin, Germany
dischellenberg@mailbox.tu-berlin.de

  1. I am conducting my PhD project at Technische Universität Berlin. My supervisors are Prof. Angela Ittel (Technische Universität Berlin); Dr. Anelis Kaiser (University of Bern), and Prof. Kerstin Palm (Humboldt University of Berlin).

Publication: Sex and Gender in F.J. Gall’s Organology

$
0
0

It took quite some time, but my article “Matters of Sex and Gender in F. J. Gall’s Organology: A Primary Approach” was finally published online in the Journal of the History of the Neurosciences. If your institution does not have a subscription to the Journal, simply email me, and I will give you access to one of 50 remaining free eprints.

Here is the abstract:

The originator of phrenology, F. J. Gall (1758–1828), saw himself as a natural scientist and physiologist. His approach consisted of brain anatomy but also of palpating skulls and inferring mental faculties. Unlike some of the philosophical principles underlying Gall’s work, his conception of sex/gender has not yet been examined in detail. In this article, I will focus on Gall’s treatment of men and women, his idea of sex differences, and how far an assumed existence of dichotomous sexes influenced his work. In examining his primary writings, I will argue that Gall held some contradictory views concerning the origin and manifestation of sex/gender characteristics, which were caused by the collision of his naturalistic ideas and internalized gender stereotypes. I will conclude that Gall did not aim at deducing or legitimizing sex/gender relations scientifically, but that he tried to express metaphysical reasons for a given social order in terms of functional brain mechanisms.

And these are the acknowledgements (only so you know whether the academic world knows about your existence now):

I am grateful to Frank Stahnisch for his support and indebted to two anonymous reviewers for helpful suggestions. Teresa Beuscher was indispensable for proper French-German translations; Anelis Kaiser, Liesel Tarquini, and Friedrich Steinle commented on earlier drafts of this article, and so did my History of Medicine class at the University of Pennsylvania under direction of David Barnes—thank you all.


There WAS Plasticity in Brain Sex Difference Research! (Part I)

$
0
0

JAS-Med 2014 at Baltimore was a fantastic conference. The papers were of really high quality, the talks engaging, and the attendees kind and curious. I hope to be able to provide pictures soon.

As you may have assumed already, I presented parts of my research project on the intersection of adult neurogenesis (ANG) research and the neuroscientific quest for sex/gender differences in brains. As mentioned earlier, it is puzzling to read the standard account of ANG history—or, more broadly, of brain plasticity—and then realize that none of these ideas of malleable brains have had influence on rigid neural and social sex/gender classifications, as Rebecca Jordan-Young, Catherine Vidal, Cordelia Fine et al., and others argue.

I have to admit (and it embarrasses me to say so) that I set out to write the history of the absence of interaction between the two neuroscientific subfields: plasticity research on the one hand and brain sex difference research on the far other hand. What I found, however, calls for a history of the process of eliminating the sex-related origin of the first accepted (re-)discovery of ANG. This process took place within the neuroscientific literature itself. Apparently, stripping ANG of its roots in sexual dimorphism research worked so well and happened so quickly that neither neuroscientists nor neurofeminists seem to have picked up on this.

But how did this happen?

First, you may want to read this pretty useful account of the development of ANG research in the second half of the 20th century: Moheb Costandi’s “Does Your Brain Produce New Cells?” (focus on the section “Fountain of eternal youth?” and the first few paragraphs of “From mice to monkeys and men” and note that MC still doubts that ANG is “real”!).

https://www.flickr.com/photos/squiddles/5681705509/sizes/l/

“Buttercup” by squiddles, CC BY-NC 2.0 

Second, note that Fernando Nottebohm, when (re-)discovering ANG in the 1980s, was researching sexual dimorphisms in song birds. He and his team realized that sex-specific behavior in song learning correlated with sex-specific brain anatomy. In an experiment in the early 1980s, they treated female canaries’ brains with testosterone. This led to both functional and structural changes in the avian brains: the hormone exposure increased the birds’ singing and enlarged specific nuclei in their brains. I am paraphrasing how Steven Goldman and Nottebohm phrased their findings in their 1983 paper: something doubles in size, this is possibly due to the growth of new neurons, and this process also occurs without any testosterone treatment, only less significantly.

We find no discussion of how hormones and exterior influences shape the brain all the way through adulthood or anything the like.

In other words, what Nottebohm and his colleagues found was not any kind of large-scale “brain plasticity” that would be transferrable to human brain sex difference research. Rather, they presented their results as a detected sexually dimorphic, seasonally dependent, and hormonally stimulated size variability of certain brain areas in songbirds. No plasticity of brain sex differences, let alone any finding that would be applicable to other species.

In order to find out why we are missing this link between brain sex difference research and this important episode in ANG research, we have to take a look at the reception of Goldman and Nottebohm’s paper. I did a quick and dirty cited reference survey.

At first glance, out of 549 citations of the paper, only 40 were articles on sexual dimorphism research. Out of the 40 sex difference papers, only 18 deal also with plasticity. That is, the majority of the quoting papers deals with proliferation, precursor cells, cell death, neurogenesis, etc. Only less than 10 % of the citing articles reference the sex research context of Nottebohm’s discovery.

Furthermore, we find:
20 references from papers on human brains, and no overlap with sex dimorphism research in all of these 20 cases,
8 referencing papers on primates, and again not a single overlap with sex,
30 referencing papers on mammals, and still no overlap with sex,
13 referencing papers on vertebrates, two of which also deal with sexual dimorphism research,
and then, finally, there was 1 salamander paper including a discussion of sex differences.

We can see that references to Goldman and Nottebohm’s 1983 paper were pretty much confined to the realm of avian brain research. The ANG part of the paper was more frequently referenced than the results in sexual dimorphism research. And only a very minor part of the referencing papers deals, like the 1983 paper, with sexual dimorphisms and ANG at the same time. It is particularly striking that not a single one out of the 549 citing papers I looked at attempts to make any inference from Nottebohm’s findings to sexual dimorphisms in mammals and primates, let alone in humans.

To summarize very quickly: brain sex difference research and ANG research were initially very closely intertwined, and not only in Nottebohm’s research.

I will talk a bit more about later similarly striking overlaps later, and, after that, reflect a bit on what this episode tells us about the emergence and stabilization of plasticity research as a new subfield within the neuroscientific discipline. But for now, back to the work I get paid for (= grading papers and prepping for class!).

“A Critical Moment”: Sex/Gender and Brain Science Conference @ UCLA, 10/23–24

$
0
0

Here is a conference announcement I should have shared with you months ago: the Foundation for Psychocultural Research at the University of Californa in Los Angeles (FPR-UCLA) is hosting a conference titled “A Critical Moment: Sex/Gender Research at the Intersection of Culture, Brain, & Behavior” this October, Friday 23rd and Saturday 24th.

Here is the announcement:

This conference occurs at a critical juncture in sex/gender research in neuroscience, anthropology, psychology, and related disciplines. New theories are utilizing a conception of the brain as dynamic, plastic, and adaptable, and of sex/gender brain and behavioral differences as subject to the influence of a broad range of biological, cultural, and social or environmental factors.

In organizing this conference, our aim is to bring the neuro- and social sciences together to consider three cross-cutting questions on sex/gender: why now? what’s fixed/changing/changeable? what’s at stake?

The proposed conference is the sixth in a series of meetings hosted by the Foundation for Psychocultural Research (FPR) at UCLA. Our mission is to support and advance interdisciplinary and integrative research and training on interactions of culture, neuroscience, psychiatry, and psychology, with an emphasis on cultural processes as central. Our primary objective is to help articulate and support the creation of transformative paradigms that address issues of fundamental clinical and social concern.

Find the registration information here.

register at a critical momentThe line-up is impressive. The list of confirmed speakers includes Sari van Anders and Anne Fausto-Sterling, whom I already mentioned in my overview of the NeuroGenderings III conference in Vienna last summer. Big-name anthropologists, psychologists, neuroscientists, artists, social scientists, and sex/gender/sexuality researchers will be there, too. The historical perspective, though, seems lacking.

I should totally go, too.

Review Paper: The Neuroscience of Pedophilia

$
0
0

The sad days are over! I just submitted the final paper for the last psychology class towards my SCAN certificate. The seminar, instructed by Teresa Pegors, is titled “Neuroscience of Human Motivation and Behavior,” and I had the more or less fabulous idea to write about pedophilia research—since it investigates into the shoreline between criminality and sexuality. That was tough, though. Not only because of the topic per se, but also since I had forgotten how hard neuroscientific(-ish) writing is. I had to correct myself over and over because it is simply too easy to write about “normal” and “abnormal” brains and desires! But, luckily, I had Georges Canguilhem watching me.

The abstract of the paper is below, and you can get a pdf of it here.

Time to take a shower and then get started with the next paper!

Neuroscientific pedophilia research has advanced over the course of last few years. Eighteen publications on the structural and functional characteristics of the brains of pedophilic individuals from the past decade, identified through a Medline search, provide the basis for this paper. With the goal to make recommendations for improvements of future research on methodological, conceptual, and ethical levels, this analysis first summarizes prevalent definitions and etiological concepts of pedophilia. It then transitions into concise summaries of individual pedophilia studies, illustrating their methodological variability. Experimental stimuli used in functional imaging studies are discussed in more detail before the concept of ‘the pedophile’, as it informs and is informed by the selection of study participants, is analyzed. Finally, the paper points to ethical concerns regarding the use of erotic visual child stimuli, the attitude towards study participants, and the use of research findings. It is suggested that future studies may benefit from attending to these concerns and from employing more coherent methods in order to make the yet inconsistent findings on the neural correlates of pedophilia more conclusive.

Book Summaries: The First 3^3 Items from My Brain List

$
0
0

Today, I’m posting my first summarizing essay for my “History of the Skull, Mind, and Brain Sciences” list for you. I’m reading the items from this list with John Tresch, who is my main advisor. Be warned: it’s 14 single-spaced pages in Palatino Linotype 11p with 1-inch margins.

Works read:

The Mind Becomes a Scientific Object
Martensen, Robert L. 2004. The Brain Takes Shape: An Early History. New York: Oxford University Press.
Hagner, Michael. 1997. Homo cerebralis: Der Wandel vom Seelenorgan zum Gehirn. Berlin: Berlin Verlag.
Breidbach, Olaf. 1997. Die Materialisierung des Ichs: Zur Geschichte der Hirnforschung im 19. und 20. Jahrhundert. Suhrkamp Taschenbuch Wissenschaft 1276. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.
Richardson, Alan. 2005. British Romanticism and the Science of the Mind. Cambridge Studies in Romanticism 47. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Mesmerism, Faces, Skulls

Goodey, C. F. 2005. “Blockheads, Roundheads, Pointy Heads: Intellectual Disability and the Brain before Modern Medicine.” Journal of the History of Behavioral Sciences 41 (2): 165–83.
Gould, Stephen J. 1996. The Mismeasure of Man. New York: W.W. Norton & Company.
Fabian, Ann. 2010. The Skull Collectors: Race, Science, and America’s Unburied Dead. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Pick, Daniel. 1989. Faces of Degeneration: A European Disorder, c.1848–c.1918. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hagner, Michael. 2004. Geniale Gehirne: Zur Geschichte der Elitegehirnforschung. Göttingen: Wallstein Verlag.
Darnton, Robert. 1968. Mesmerism and the End of the Enlightenment in France. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Winter, Alison. 1998. Mesmerized: Powers of Mind in Victorian Britain. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Greenblatt, Samuel H. 1995. “Phrenology in the Science and Culture of the 19th Century.” Neurosurgery 37 (4): 790–805. doi:10.1227/00006123-199510000-00025 .
Davies, John D. 1955. Phrenology, Fad and Science: A 19th-Century American Crusade. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Tomlinson, Stephen. 2005. Head Masters: Phrenology, Secular Education, and Nineteenth-Century Social Thought. Tuscaloosa: University of Alabama Press.
de Giustino, David. 1975. Conquest of Mind: Phrenology and Victorian Social Thought. London: Croom Helm.
Shapin, Steven. 1975. “Phrenological Knowledge and the Social Structure of Early Nineteenth-Century Edinburgh.” Annals of Science 32 (3): 219–43. doi:10.1080/00033797500200261 .
Cooter, Roger J. 1984. The Cultural Meaning of Popular Science: Phrenology and the Organization of Consent in Nineteenth-Century Britain. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Young, Robert M. 1985. “The Role of Psychology in the Nineteenth-Century Evolutionary Debate” In Darwin’s Metaphor: Nature’s Place in Victorian Culture, edited by Robert M. Young, 56–78. Cambridge, New York: Cambridge University Press.
van Wyhe, John. 2004. Phrenology and the Origins of Victorian Scientific Naturalism. Aldershot: Ashgate.
Lyons, Sherrie L. 2009. Species, Serpents, Spirits, and Skulls: Science at the Margins in the Victorian Age. Albany: SUNY Press.
Russett, Cynthia E. 1989. Sexual Science: The Victorian Construction of Womanhood. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Malane, Rachel A. 2005. Sex in Mind: The Gendered Brain in Nineteenth-Century Literature and Mental Sciences. Studies in Nineteenth-Century British Literature 22. New York: Peter Lang.

Physiology
Daston, Lorraine J. 1978. “British Responses to Psycho-Physiology, 1860–1900.” Isis 69 (2): 192–208. doi:10.1086/352003 .
Harrington, Anne. 1989. Medicine, Mind, and the Double Brain: A Study in Nineteenth-Century Thought . Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Young, Robert M. 1970. Mind, Brain and Adaptation in the Nineteenth Century: Cerebral Localization and Its Biological Context from Gall to Ferrier. New York: Clarendon Press.
Star, Susan L. 1989. Regions of the Mind: Brain Research and the Quest for Scientific Certainty. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Hagner, Michael. 2012. “The Electrical Excitability of the Brain: Toward the Emergence of an Experiment.” Journal of the History of the Neurosciences 21 (3): 237–49. doi:10.1080/0964704X.2011.595634 .

The texts in this section describe how the mind became an object of scientific investigation in Europe and, to a lesser extent, in North America between the 16th and the 19th centuries. Three major themes across the 27 books, articles, and book chapters are 1) how the mind was materialized and located in the brain, 2) what counts as a scientific approach to the mind/brain complex, and 3) the extent to which studies of the mind and brain were motivated by or influenced social, political, and evolutionary thought. The works discussed below have been published between the years 1955 and 2012. The texts from the 1970s and 1980s alone can illustrate almost the entire variety of approaches historians and sociologists have taken over the past 60 years to assess the brain and mind sciences in the long 19th century. Although written by scholars from the same generation, some of these works are progressivist intellectual histories, others strictly focus on the social context in which the knowledge was produced, some focus on practical challenges scientists are faced in the lab and in promoting their research, and yet another group of scholars tries to disentangle ‘real’ science and pseudoscience or non-science.

With The Brain Takes Shape, the late physician, bioethicist, and medical historian Robert Martensen provided his readership with a study of the emergence of the brain as the core of human life and intellect in the 16th and 17th centuries. His introductory chronicle from the Reformation to the end of the 17th century sets the stage for his main argument: that the concept of a cerebral personhood, as opposed to a humoral bodily system, emerged only in the second half of the 17th century. In particular, he argues that this shift was mainly initiated in England, where the ideas of the Reformation and the Scientific Revolution clashed in particular; the church as well as the monarchy had to defend their authority while natural philosophy tried to separate itself from religion and politics. As a result, the very concepts of ‘life’ and ‘body’ changed and anatomy as well as physiology were established as fields of inquiry.

In the main body of the book, Martensen draws on a wide range of archival and published sources and elucidates his argument with some well-chosen illustrations. He discusses two natural philosophers as exemplars for larger groups of thinkers, R. Descartes and T. Willis, and describes the extent to which their cerebral models of the brain were reactions to and informed by contemporary cultural developments and political struggles. In chapter 8, Martensen explains how natural philosophy changed towards the late 17th century in that it split up into ‘scientific’ empiricism and metaphysics, disposing of earlier inquiries characterized by the omnipresence of divine notions and laws. T. Sydenham and J. Locke, Martensen argues, were major agents in stripping Willis’s doctrines of their religious connotations and promoting similar but empiricized views of cerebral bodies—without acknowledging Willis. Martensen closes with a chapter that explores the persistence of the cerebral personhood over the 19th and 20th centuries, identifying an unprecedented neuroscientific movement to elevate “likeness” (or empirical knowledge, or biology) above “presence” (or metaphysics, or phenomenology).

Michael Hagner’s Homo cerebralis, first published in 1997, provides a cultural history of how the brain, understood as the seat of an immaterial soul since R. Descartes, evolved into a material scientific object over the course of the 18th and 19th centuries. Hagner’s main argument is that this change in the meaning of the brain as an object of investigation preceded the Darwinian and Freudian revolutions in human self-perception. After abandoning the search for the organ of the soul in the brain around 1800, brain and mind researchers tried to access the self on the brain’s material basis.

After describing how the rise of the human sciences in the 18th century led to a redefinition of Descartes’s abstract organ of the soul into an anatomical entity that could be detected in vivisections, Hagner proceeds to illustrating the huge success of F.J. Gall’s organology and its reception in the field of mind and brain research. According to Hagner, however, only investigations by Romantic natural philosophers like K.F. Burdach and C.G. Carus marked the transition from inductive brain research to the late-19th-century tradition of experimental physiological brain localization. Hagner considers the unsuccessful revolution of 1848 as a crucial turning point in the orientation of physiologists: a new realism manifested itself in an abandonment of all scientific searches for the soul and led to purely materialistic approaches to brain parts, electrical excitability and their connections to reflexes and mental functions. The success of physiological brain localization, Hagner shows, heavily rested on the increasing collaboration between psychiatrists, physiologists, and anatomists towards the later 19th century. Only this merger of disciplines allowed for a stabilization of the brain, Hagner argues. The existence of the organ of the mind was not questioned by any of these developments, he concludes, but it was no longer a topic of interest within the mind and brain sciences.

This observation resonates with the late philosopher, biologist, and historian of science Olaf Breidbach’s argument that the past 200 years have seen a significant shift in the questions pursued around the brain and mind. Hagner focused on the changes of the brain as an epistemic object from the 17th through the 19th centuries, whereas Breidbach is more interested in the intellectual development of ideas of the self in the 19th and 20th centuries. In his monograph Die Materialisierung des Ichs, Breidbach traces the emergence of scientific inquiries into the brain and mind with a particular focus on how these investigations have changed the views of the self. He begins his intellectual history with late-18th-century searches for the organ of the soul and ends with 20th-century theories in the philosophy of mind; in the meantime, Breidbach covers the work and ideas of virtually every white European brain or mind researcher. He argues that it was a change in the ways in which questions about the self were asked that allowed for the pervasive biologization of the self and mind in the past 200 years (from the question of what is the brain to the question of how it works, p. 13), not any grand insight that was revealed merely by studying the brain over generations.

Furthermore, Breidbach shows that differing discourses around the brain and mind coexisted at any time and helped define the approach of later scientists and thinkers, often grounded in the philosophical ideas of the time. In particular, Breidbach argues that 20th-century knowledge of the brain rests on 19th-century concepts; the more recent approaches to the brain, including cybernetics and molecular biology, are only methodologically refined and do not pose a conceptual break with late-19th-century ideas of how the brain works. Finally, Breidbach concludes that no coherent theory about the ways in which the self is materialized in the brain has been postulated yet, and he doubts that this will ever be possible.

English Professor Alan Richardson’s third monograph, British Romanticism and the Science of the Mind, examines the impact of the rising materialization of the mind as it is spelled out in Hagner’s and Breidbach’s monographs on English literature during the Romantic era (1790–1830). The analysis focuses on the notion of what Richardson calls “neural Romanticism” (ch. 1) in the works of Samuel Coleridge, William Wordsworth, John Keats, and Jane Austen. Drawing also on archival sources, for instance, notes from the scientific lectures the writers used to attend or the letters they wrote, Richardson provides deeper insight into the entanglement of brain science and English literature as Rachel Malane, for instance, can provide (see below). With an eye to the alleged similarities between the concerns of contemporary neuroscience and romantic brain and mind research, Richardson investigates into the reflection of the “innovative, exciting, and threatening” potential of this science in Romantic literature (p. xv). He argues that the consideration of new scientific theories helps solve puzzles in literary studies pertaining to (changes in) the meanings of words and metaphors in English Romantic literature.

According to Richardson, important characteristics of these researchers’ ideas of the brain are 1) that they believe that the mind is located in the brain and that this brain is active, even if the rest of the body is asleep, and 2) that this brain activity rests on biological instead of mechanical processes. The belief in a similarity between the brains of humans and other animals was also a widely held Romantic notion. Richardson furthermore stresses that commonly assumed geographical and disciplinary borders were regularly crossed in the Romantic period, including the science/pseudoscience boundary. F.J. Gall is deemed to be one of the most overtly Romantic brain scientists by Richardson who influenced some of the mentioned writers.

Christopher Goodey’s paper on “Blockheads, Roundheads, Pointy Heads” is an analysis of the continuities in the assessment of what we would nowadays call mental disability. Goodey traces abnormal heads, abnormal intellects, and abnormal personalities since Galenic times, arguing that the mindset of contemporary researchers in their assessment of mental disability is similar to early modern scholars’ theorizing of monstrosity, but not to their models of cognitive impairment. This pathologization of intellectual disability or monstrosity, Goodey argues, has its origins in the late 17th century, a time during which causes for physical abnormalities and demonic forces merged. In the work of J. Locke and others’, Goodey detects a conflation of the “unnatural” (according to Aristoteles: unusual, but caused by natural forces) and the “preternatural” (caused by supernatural forces from outside the body, such as gods or devils), the origin of the concept of abnormality he assumes at the core of contemporary assessments of mental disability. Goodey’s paper complements the above-mentioned works that focus on the materialization of healthy minds and brains.

Stephen J. Gould’s The Mismeasure of Man, first published in 1981, is a 200-year history of the quantification of allegedly innate intellectual capacity in humans and the notions of biological determinism—or scientific racism—that surround it. He calls the two “fallacies” he concerns himself with “reification” and “ranking” (p. 56). Polemically and with great attention to detail in the primary sources, at times even with scientific rigor, Gould aims at debunking the myth of objective science and neutral data as he discusses five major scientific attempts of linearly ranking human intelligence, from well-meaning flawed science to deliberate fabrication of data in the interest of one’s own theory: S.G. Morton’s and others’ measurement of cranial volumes; P.P. Broca’s and others’ assessment of brain weight and volume; recapitulation theories and C. Lombroso’s criminal anthropology; 20th-century American hereditarian theories of the IQ, in particular R.M. Yerkes’s advertisement of psychometric tests in the US Army; as well as C. Burt’s studies of identical twins and the development of the factor analysis to support G. Spearman’s theory about general intelligence. Gould shows how the preoccupation with hierarchically quantifying allegedly innate intelligence persisted while measurements moved from the outside and the inside of the skull in the 19th century to mental function in the 20th century. Gould does not stop at identifying subjective interpretations and skewed measurements.

Ann Fabian’s third monograph, The Skull Collectors, narrates the story of S. Morton and his followers’ acquisition and study of human skulls. Fabian focuses on the time before and during the American Civil War, but she also connects them to 20th-century controversies around repatriation and the revival of ideas similar to Morton’s in 20th-century genetics. This study zooms in on one of the episodes discussed by Gould, but Fabian’s main argument extends Gould’s point that Morton postulated a linear hierarchy of different groups of humans and that he did so motivated by his racist presuppositions. Fabian shows that the history of craniometry as “’scientific racism’” (p. 2 and many more) illustrates the deep connections between American history, the history of theories about race, and the history of burial practices and commemoration of the dead. Fabian explicates in rich detail the work involved in obtaining skulls and transforming them into scientific or museum artifacts; her archival sources, in particular the correspondence between craniometrists and skull collectors, allow her to draw a vivid picture of the mindset surrounding the alleged proof of the superiority of the Caucasian race and to show how crucial networking was for Morton’s success.

Faces of Degeneration, Daniel Pick’s first book, is an assessment of the scientific and intellectual concept of “degeneration” in the second half of the long 19th century or, rather, the Foucaultian “discourse” around this topic. Focusing on France (particularly the writings of B.A. Morel), Italy (C. Lombroso), and England (H. Maudsley), Pick shows how degeneration was promoted from one in many to the central tropic of scientific and anthropological investigation and how the field shifted from diagnosing degeneration in individuals to medicalizing entire groups. According to Pick, this shift was partially a consequence of the rise of sociology and the desire for medical mass-management of the masses in growing metropolitan societies. Mass democracy, socialism, and becoming a member of “the crowd” arose to the new threats of human modernity over the course of the later 19th century (p. 223). Degeneration discourse, Picks suggests, was used as a means of power and to establish scientific authority, evidenced both in the emphasis on the professions of degeneration researchers as well as the naturalistic, empirical language they used. He weaves together themes familiar from Gould’s and Goodey’s work into a European intellectual-political history.

In his accessible and richly illustrated monography Geniale Gehirne, first published in 2004, Hagner traces the concept he calls the elite brain from the late 18th to the 20th century. He inquires into the extent to which the search for material manifestations of genius contributed to the construction of the homo cerebralis as discussed in his earlier work. Partially overlapping and extending his earlier study by one century, Hagner analyzes the contexts in which the elite brain has become an object of study in different fields within the mind and brain sciences and to what extent these scientifically constructed elite brains, laden with moral and political meaning, have been transformed from scientific into cultural objects and have thus impacted the commemoration and perceived authority of alleged intellectual elites in the broader society.

Hagner locates a revival of exceptionalism research in the brain and mind sciences and the shift towards research on natural elite brains—as opposed to brains of admired individuals—around 1900. With resemblance to Pick’s and Gould’s studies, Hagner illustrates that this transformation was aided by eugenic theories and institutionally facilitated by the founding of the international Central Commission for Brain Research in 1903, which enabled researchers all over Europe and in the United States to collaborate and systematically classify and assess different types of brains. According to Hagner, this depersonalization in research on exceptional brains was also a cultural response to the demise of the type of the German intellectual and statesman. Instead of holding up exemplary personalities like in the 19th century, Hagner sees the early 20th century characterized by a deliberate use of the concept of elite brains as a form of “biopolitics” (p. 17) in the Weimar Republic and the early Soviet Union. Conceptually, Hagner argues, not much changed in the 20th century as compared to the 19th century, only the methods and physiological theories were more refined.

Robert Darnton’s first book inquires into the evolution of radical political thought in pre-revolutionary France. Mesmerism and the End of the Enlightenment in France draws from published material and formerly secret manuscripts. Darnton tells France’s cultural history through the lens of investigations into animal magnetism as proposed by F.A. Mesmer in Paris. Mesmerism functions as an illustrative example of the ways in which popular science was used to promote and at the same time benefitted from and incorporated radical political views. Darnton makes an even stronger argument, though, and suggests that Mesmer’s popular science and later versions of it shattered the Enlightenment in France by overriding the quest for reason and order with a longing for sensation, spectacle, and change and the hierarchy of privilege and scientific exclusivity with popular mysticism for the unlearned.

Darnton’s monograph virtually begins where Martensen’s ends and provides an overview of the French literate society’s fascination with technological and popular scientific spectacle in the 1780s in his richly illustrated first chapter. Darnton wants to prove his point that: “The progressive divorce of science from theology in the eighteenth century did not free science from fiction” (p. 12). Mesmerists, Darnton shows, voiced political discontent in a predominantly unpolitical, scientific tone, despite the always-existing “underground current of radicalism” (p. 104). The desire for change had united the mesmerists, but since they did not share any concrete political visions for a post-revolutionary society, the movement dispersed and former allies became enemies in the late 1780s. Early 19th-century mesmerism, Darnton shows, was mostly practiced as mystic philosophy, but it regained some of its political force leading up to the attempted revolution of 1848, during which the two core principles of liberty and health were upheld again in the hope they may lead to a democratic society.

Alison Winter’s first book, Mesmerized, sheds light on the mesmerist movement in Victorian England in the mid-19th century after it had made its way to the isles. Drawing on a wide range of correspondence and personal manuscripts as well as contemporary journal and newspaper publications in Great Britain and colonial India, Winter shows how mesmerism impacted virtually all realms of British cultural life: religion, music, literal art, politics, as well as science and medicine. She demonstrates that mesmerism was everything but a fringe activity between 1830 and 1860 and that the question of intellectual and social authority was at the center of the controversies around mesmerism. Winter puts particular focus on the social and technological changes during these three decades of mesmerism and reform in Britain and argues that mesmerism was used as a tool to expose hidden assumptions and point to social inequalities, that it blurred the boundaries between public and private life, and that it broadened the range of possible modes of consciousness. By the 1870s, when physiology and medicine were transformed into laboratory sciences, mesmerism lost is function as a social mirror within the Victorian society as it was absorbed by other movements such as psychic research and psychoanalysis.

In “Phrenology in the Science and Culture of the 19th Century,” Samuel Greenblatt, a retired neurosurgeon, argues that F.J. Gall laid the foundations of contemporary neuroscience in the early 19th century in that he insisted on a materialistic approach to the brain and suggested the localization of individual faculties. Greenblatt summarizes the phrenological movement since Gall in continental Europe (until the 1820s), in Great Britain (in the 1820s and 1830s) and in the US (1820s to 1840s). He also touches briefly on brain localization in Europe in the second half of the 19th century, emphasizing that these scientists shared ideological convictions with Gall but labored hard to distinguish themselves from this alleged pseudoscience. Greenblatt further emphasizes that the success of phrenology in the US derived from the phrenologists’, mainly the Fowler family’s, targeting the lower classes, an argument that is in line with Winter’s and Darnton’s analyses pertaining to the audience of mesmerism. However, Gall and the European phrenologists had mainly advocated for theoretical phrenology that did not seem useful or accessible to uneducated individuals, Greenblatt argues.

John Davies’s Phrenology, Fad and Science is one of the oldest monographs about phrenology. He wrote it at a time when phrenology was widely discarded as a pseudoscience in historical circles, with the exception of a few medical historians who aimed at reading phrenology as a precursor to 20th-century neuroanatomy and physiology—as Greenblatt still did in 1995. Davies’s intervention was to look at phrenology as a popular movement of self-improvement that rested on scientific promises. Davies also agrees that F.J. Gall was a precursor of 20th-century neuroscience since he was the first scholar to aim at an ‘objective’ study of the human mind and brain, leaving behind any biases. In line with Greenblatt’s and Tomlinson’s accounts, Davies presents phrenology in America as a movement that built on J.G. Spurzheim’s optimistic views about humankind, in contrast to Gall, who seemed to be less convinced of the perfectibility of humans and located many anti-social drives on the cortex.

Davies suggests, in line with Hagner’s argument from almost half a century later, as I indicated above, that Darwinism and Freudianism took over the spot held by phrenology. This stands in contrast to John van Wyhe’s, Robert M. Young’s, and Roger Cooter’s works on the intellectual continuities between phrenology and evolutionary theory (see below). Davies emphasizes in line with works mentioned in the following that phrenology crucially influenced 19th-century fiction and that it had a major influence on American progressive movements, for example, in education, psychiatry, medicine, and penology; he also shows, however, how phrenology adopted structures, practices, and ideologies from other fields, such as religion, alternative medicine, and mesmerism. Phrenology, Davies concludes, posed an option for Americans to develop an optimistic secular morality on a scientific basis and with a strong social agenda, but it did not permeate everyday-life. In particular, he argues, phrenology put too much focus on individualism and liberty to have that strong of an impact in any non-American society.

Professor of Education Stephen Tomlinson’s first book, Head Masters, tells the story of phrenological influences on education and educational reform movements in pre-Darwinian 19th-century Britain and the US. Though he never explicitly states it, Tomlinson illustrates that the reverse influence was significant as well. He argues that most notably H. Mann’s and S.G. Howe’s requests for adjusted school curricula, the introduction of therapeutic asylums, a change in the prison system, special schools for individuals with physical and mental disabilities, and even the American welfare system were derived from G. Combe’s phrenological system. This was possible, Tomlinson explains, because J.G. Spurzheim and Combe transformed F.J. Gall’s purely materialist organology into a “broad eugenic social philosophy” (p. 76), that is, a phrenological system that allowed for both inherited qualities and environmental influences and thus called for pedagogical and disciplinary secular reforms on the individual as well as the institutional level.

This emphasis on the reformist potential of phrenology reiterates Greenblatt’s point, but whereas Greenblatt assumes that Combe was too much of a theoretical phrenologist to reach lower classes, Tomlinson argues that Combe significantly impacted middle-class reformers not long after his publication The Constitution of Man (1828). To Tomlinson, Combe was “one of the most important and influential educators of the century” (p. xiv). Tomlinson spells this out in great detail, tracing the similarities in ideas between educators and phrenologists, drawing mostly on secondary literature as well as published contemporary books, articles, and reports. Eventually, Tomlinson suggests that all educational reforms must be based on some scientific foundation; he argues that Combe provided mid-19th-century reformers with a physiological theory of heredity and exercise that instilled, among other developments, Mann’s and Howe’s racist, classist, and sexist politics of positive eugenics in New England.

Historian David de Giustino’s first book Conquest of Mind is a history of the Combe family’s investment in phrenology and the status of popular science in Victorian Britain more broadly. Drawing on a wide variety of published sources (newspapers, periodicals, journal articles, books, reports) and archival collections, in particular Combe’s correspondence, de Giustino illustrates the deep entanglement of phrenology with the British educational reform movement in the 1840s and 1850s and thus provides the Combe-centric complement to Tomlinson’s work.

De Giustino argues that phrenology was appealing to the Victorian lower classes because it was phrased in terms that could easily be understood by lay people, it explained and was in line with contemporary morals, and yet it was “hopeful” (p. 74) in that it offered a method for self-improvement and advertised an individualized concept of society. To a notable number of individuals from the higher classes, including scientists and physicians, it seemed equally attractive because it was in line with contemporary philosophical theories and moral values, it attempted to reject metaphysics, it was built on the manual study of hundreds of material heads, and it admitted modestly that it was not a complete science yet. Since de Giustino also illustrates how heterogeneous phrenology was, one wonders how much weight should be given to de Giustino’s and his colleagues’ generalizing claims about “phrenology’s” reformist potential.

Steven Shapin wrote his article “Phrenological Knowledge and the Social Structure of Early Nineteenth-Century Edinburgh” and similar papers against purely intellectual accounts of the Edinburgh debates between phrenologists and anti-phrenologists in the early and mid-19th century. Even though the article is a response to the work of Geoffrey Cantor, Shapin’s critique would similarly apply to de Giustino’s work in that it explains the controversy around phrenology as a disagreement about scientific ideas and methodological concepts. Setting an example for how to craft a sociology of knowledge, Shapin presents in words and tables that phrenologists consisted of individuals from marginalized groups in the Edinburgh society and that the rising mercantilism endangered the Edinburgh elites’ longing for social coherence and “’common sense’” (p. 238) as much as the phrenological doctrine of inborn individual differences did. In this changing social structure, Shapin argues, both the phrenologists’ support of the working and lower middle classes and their opposition to established elite institutions were growing.

Shapin, like the aforementioned authors, also puts emphasis on the reformist aspect of phrenology. But his argument that the originally ‘nature’-focused phrenology shifted its doctrine towards a more ‘nurture’-centered model for strategical reasons is new. As Shapin argues, a theory of innate cerebral and mental differences caused disagreement among established circles, but the notion that self-knowledge and training could change one’s physical and mental constitution found support amongst the environmentally oriented conservative circles. Thus, some of the anti-phrenologists supported their reformist claims, a situation that was, as Shapin suggests, foreseen by the phrenologists and gave more weight to their demands. In opposition to Robert Young’s student Roger Cooter, Shapin thus argues that phrenology did not (only) make an industrial stratification of society acceptable; it also benefited from these new values.

With his first book, The Cultural Meaning of Popular Science, Cooter has broadened and deepened de Giustino’s analysis and provided a study of Victorian phrenology that extends way beyond G. Combe. Cooter also uses Combe’s archival papers, but he complements them with a vast amount of further archival papers, tractates, reports, parliamentary papers, and phrenological journals. Cooter follows Davies and de Giustino in treating phrenology as a popularized science, admitting that it looks like “a Dickensian caricature of science” nowadays (p. 9), which makes it the perfect case study to investigate into the demarcations between science and non-science or society and science, a view also held by Sherrie Lyons (see below).

Cooter’s study of phrenology’s social and political impact is framed by A. Gramsci’s Marxist model of egemonia and heavily laden with references to Marx, Foucault, and the Frankfurt School, resulting in a rather pessimistic study of Victorian England. Cooter explains how his actors upheld conservative social structures without noticing. He mentions, for instance, that Combe’s upbringing led him to formulate a phrenological system that resonated very well with the new capitalist-industrialist order. This interpretation stands in stark contrast to Tomlinson’s argument that Combe was invested in educational reform because he had left behind and wanted to eradicate any Calvinist structures that had traumatized himself as a child. Eventually, Cooter argues that phrenology was like a religion to its followers; it changed the public’s understanding of the mind and brain and produced a new form of consent that paved the way for a new industrial social order. This reminds of Winter’s argument that mesmerism was a crucial factor in developing a concept of social consent. But whereas Winter argues that mesmerist theories of the unconscious allowed for “the development of a psychology of public judgment” (Mesmerized, p. 8), Cooter’s explanation is more hegemonic: a new theory of the mind that is characterized by “natural laws” (p. 11, italics i.o.), the medicalization of mental disturbance, and individual—or social—inequality made capitalism and the cultural changes that went along with it socially acceptable.

Robert M. Young is a psychotherapist as well as a historian and philosopher of science who left academia in the 1970s to continue his intellectual and political work without institutional affiliation. In “The Role of Psychology in the Nineteenth-Century Evolutionary Debate,” first published in 1973, Young shows that evolutionary thought has been part of psychology even in the late 18th century, with “evolution” being defined as the belief “that the origin of man occurred by means of the continuous operation of natural laws and not by special creation” (p. 57). Mental, social, cultural, and physical life all became subsets of science in this system of thought. This conviction of the intellectual continuity between phrenology and evolutionary theory is shared by Cooter and explicated by John van Wyhe in more detail (see below). C. Darwin’s ideology, Young argues, was not original but derived from earlier investigations in geology and psychology; new was only the evidence Darwin presented. The bold argument that Young makes in this essay is that psychology (i.e., associationism, phrenology, and neurophysiology) lay at the core of evolutionary theory or, in other words, that “evolutionary theory … is applied psychology” (p. 69, italics i.o.).

John van Wyhe’s first book, Phrenology and the Origins of Victorian Scientific Naturalism, complements older accounts of phrenology in that it emphasizes the struggle for power in phrenological and anti-phrenological individuals. Van Wyhe refines Shapin’s account of phrenology as a debate between social groups as well as Cooter’s description of a hegemonic culture. Focusing not only on phrenological publications but also drawing on a wide range of newspapers as well as popular and scientific periodicals, van Wyhe argues that phrenology was one of the most important sources of “scientific naturalism,” which was introduced by a few individuals as a main tactic of seeking social power and scientific authority. Van Wyhe argues that naturalism became one of the pillars of Victorian scientific thought. He also takes into consideration the early continental European organological sources and compares Gall’s naturalism with later British versions of the concept.

Most striking in comparison with older scholarship on phrenology is van Wyhe’s argument that phrenology was not a reform movement, precisely due to its character of being a means of personal elevation rather than an intellectual and social movement carried by a more or less coherent social group. The emphasis on the heterogeneity of individuals within phrenology resonates with similar remarks in de Giustino’s and Lyons’s works, but van Wyhe spells out the disparity in personal motives in more detail. In part, this monograph is an explication of Cooter’s claim that naturalism preceded Darwinism and stands in opposition to the works of Davies and Hagner (2000), in which phrenology and Darwinism are identified as two intellectually very distinct movements.

Sherrie Lyons’s monograph Species, Serpents, Spirits, and Skulls is an investigation into what makes a fringe science become an accepted scientific discipline. Drawing mostly on secondary literature, she compares the abandoned fields of sea serpent research, phrenology, and spiritualism with evolutionary science, which became a well-respected field of study. Lyons uses her deeply interwoven 19th-century case studies to argue that “the distinction between science and pseudoscience is not sharp” (p. xi) and that the content of doctrines is not the reason for why some fields remain at the margins while others managed to move to the center of scientific investigation. “Social as well as cognitive factors” and issues of (un)successful professionalization crucially molded the scientific landscape, she argues (p. xii). The far-reaching concluding chapter spells out the question of boundaries between science and non-science with the help of two more contemporary case studies: fossils “as possible links between myth and science” (p. 16) and evolutionary psychology, in particular regarding postulated sex/gender differences, which Lyons’s feminist account sees in line with phrenology in its attempt to scientifically explain the human mind and nature.

In her chapter on phrenology, Lyons emphasizes the heterogeneous nature of the field that reached from “a marginal science well on its way to becoming part of the scientific mainstream” to “quackery” (p. 5). She illustrates how deeply entrenched phrenology was with then contemporary intellectual, political, and social controversies. A threat to physicians, philosophers, upper classes, and the church, Lyons shows, phrenology was more of a social movement than a (pseudo)science and should thus be called a “nonscience” (p. 178). This emphasis on the reformative aspect of phrenology resonates well with the works of Greenblatt, Tomlinson, and Davies. Her identification of similarities between the evolutionary ideas in F.J. Gall’s and Darwin’s theories is in line with Young’s, Cooter’s, and van Wyhe’s scholarship. Lyons argues that the striking ideological similarity between the two fields does not allow for an intellectual explanation of why phrenology was dismissed in the second half of the 19th century whereas Darwinism rose to power and acceptance. It is surprising that Lyons still seems to hold a teleological view of a “self-correcting” science that allows us to gain an “increasingly accurate view of the material world” (p. 16).

Late historian Cynthia E. Russett’s third book, Sexual Science, also ties in evolutionary thought with theories of the mind and brain. Russett presents Victorian-style naturalist explanations for the inferiority of women—and children as well as non-white and lower-class individuals—during the first decades of first-wave feminism up to 1920 in Europe and in the United States. She draws on contemporary publications, mostly from white male scientists, but also from a few women whose writings modified the scientific arguments but reiterated similar themes of difference. After mentioning several strands of phrenology as exceptional science because it left room for female intellectual potential, Russett proceeds to show that theories of sex differences in skull shape, skull size, brain volume, brain weight, intellectual capacity, and energy metabolism were mostly carried out to attest female inferiority. This conclusion was not derived from objective, skeptical, empirical practice, she argues, but aimed at solidifying social differences and creating an efficient and easy-to-govern industrial society; but this latter argument is not as clearly spelled out as in Cooter’s work.

Russett’s emphasis on the biased approach to female heads and the attempt to locate them below white male heads in a hierarchical order resonates very well with Gould’s account in The Mismeasure of Man. Russett provides a more contextualized account of the authority of science to speak to the subject of a hierarchically ordered humanity, however. Her main goal is not to debunk the myth of objective science but to weave in already familiar accounts of scientific discrimination in the context of physical anthropology, theories of recapitulation and sexual selection, ideas of male variability and female homogeneity, and conservation theory. She illustrates how generations of scientists in different fields, before and after Darwin, have drawn from similar ideological repositories to create a pervasive and persistent net of naturalist explanations for female inferiority and the necessity of sex-based division of labor. A major difference between Gould’s and Russett’s work is that Russett believes that her account of scientific sexism reflects historical anxieties of nations transitioning into ‘modernism’ (including genetics, endocrinology, and IQ tests), whereas Gould is convinced that scientific racism persisted and progressed.

English Literature graduate Rachel Malane’s first book, Sex in Mind, is a literary cultural complement to Russett’s monograph. Malane analyses of how Victorian writers, most notably Charlotte Brontë, Wilkie Collins, and Thomas Hardy, integrated scientific theories about mind- and brain-related sex/gender differences into their work and how the authors at the same time promoted these scientific theories and fueled further investigations into the topic; she calls this relationship between brain science and literary culture “mutually supportive” (p. xii). Malane focuses on different novels that span almost the entire second half of the 19th century and means to prove that the obsession with physiological correlates of sex and gender roles were pervasive in Victorian culture. Despite the differences between the authors, she argues, all of the personalities they create rest on an assumed biological difference lying at the heart of the minds of males versus females. Eventually, Malane argues, “when we find a concept, such as the gendered mind, deeply embedded in [science and literature], we can argue that such a concept is central to the internal logic of a society” (p. 203).

The “British Responses to Psycho-Physiology” identified by Lorraine Daston in her paper implicitly suggest that the legacy of phrenology made it particularly hard for British scientists to respond to the new experimental, materialistic sciences of the mind in the second half of the 19th century that have been described by Breidbach, Richardson, and Greenblatt. Drawing on the writings of well-known researchers who explicitly investigated into psychological phenomena and writers who concerned themselves with the topic, Daston argues that a decision between a naturalistic approach, resulting in compartmentalized consciousness and an exclusion of volition from the discipline, and introspective empiricism seemed inevitable to late 19th-century researchers. Daston connects the importance of the question of volition and responsibility to the strong focus of British psychology on social matters, such as education and penology. The literature on phrenology, which Daston does not mention, suggests a close parallel between early British brain research, that is, phrenology, and social reform movements—much more so than it was the case in continental Europe. It seems plausible that “the pressures to harmonize psychological and ethical perspectives” that resulted from “the marked practical slant” identified by Daston in the British psychology of the time (p. 197) is a result of the strong connection of phrenology with legal and pedagogical matters in the same region a few decades earlier.

Anne Harrington traces the scientific concept of brain (a)symmetry in her monograph Medicine, Mind, and the Double Brain. She calls her work “a study in conceptual history” intended to provide “a reliable map” to the issue of the double brain in 19th-century brain science (p. 3). Harrington focuses on the years 1860 to 1910, but she begins her analysis with a quick overview of searches for the seat of the soul in the early 19th century and extends her study to some developments in the 20th century. She draws mainly from French published sources but also includes several British, North American, and German publications to support her argument that brain asymmetry was a crucial topic in 19th-century brain science.

Harrington’s description of Broca’s and his followers’ investigations into the localization of language and other characteristics starting in the 1860s makes up the major part of her book. Harrington explains how Broca turned the study of a language area in the brain into an inquiry into human exceptionalism. In this context, Harrington sheds light on the debate of whether brain asymmetry is innate or a consequence of different rates of maturity in the two halves of the brain and, thus, whether human exceptionality originates from an inborn ability to speak or from a significant potential to learn and acquire language despite being born with a brain not much different from any other animal brain. Broca himself settled on the latter explanation.

Young dedicated his first book, Mind, Brain and Adaptation in the Nineteenth Century, to his teachers, one of which is Richard Rorty. The monograph analyzes published 19th-century works in the field of brain and mind research from F.J. Gall to Harrington’s and Susan L. Star’s (see below) actors who engaged in electrophysiology and brain localization in the late 19th century. Young’s study illustrates how psychology became an experimental science or, in Young’s own words, its “development away from philosophy and toward general biology” (p. vii). Young studies the end of the Cartesian dualism in brain localization, a field he interprets as the linking of the mind to the brain. His second concern is the study of the functions of the brain, which is, to Young, an account of how scientists perceived the interaction of humans and their environment. Young suggests that his historical account of Gall’s and later attempts to foster brain science, rather than speculation about the mind, adds to 20th-century debates within the mind and brain sciences, in particular pertaining to the diversity of approaches within this field. In particular, Young hopes to illustrate the extent to which philosophical considerations of the mind have hindered the progress of brain science and that the desiderata of Cartesian dualism should be eliminated from the field.

In line with the aforementioned authors who do not count Gall towards the phrenological reformers, in particular Greenblatt, Davies, Tomlinson, and de Giustino, Young distinguishes between Gall’s organology and the later phrenological movement. To Young, Gall was the first natural brain scientist and the later 19th-century localizationists picked up the torch that had been left behind by the phrenologists whom he regards as pseudoscientists. Since Young excludes the phrenologists from his analysis of scientific studies of the mind and brain, this account does not clearly reflect his, Cooter’s, and van Wyhe’s strong conviction that evolutionary ideas had been essential to phrenology.

Late sociologist Susan L. Star’s first monograph complicates the progressivist story told by Young. Regions of the Mind is a study of the “scientific work” (p. 1) involved in making brain localization theory acceptable throughout the brain and mind sciences. Drawing on published works and archival sources, including laboratory notebooks, Star attends to scientific and philosophical controversies around the links between mind and behavior from 1870 to 1906, when C.S. Sherrington published The Integrative Action of the Nervous System, a work that established localization theory in the so-called Western world, according to Star. She describes these decades as a time characterized by the debate between “localizationists” (mainly in England) and “diffusionists” (individuals in continental Europe and the United States), arguing that “inconstant correlation” (p. 6), the circumstance that similar lesions did not always cause the same deficits, was one of the biggest problems the localizationists encountered and at the same time one of the easiest targets for their opponents.

To Star, “scientific work”—besides the ‘usual’ pains of preparing animals for experiments, disseminating one’s viewpoints, connecting with colleagues, etc.—designates the labor that is involved in adhering to a theory despite apparent counterevidence and adapting it slightly to integrate the inconsistency as a non-incommensurability. As a consequence, she illustrates, the theories of localizationists in particular were flexible and sometimes hardly distinct from diffusionist accounts. Diffusionists and localizationists were distinguishable mainly on the basis of the camps they associated with. In the end, the localizationists officially won the debate, mostly because they were institutionalized, well-connected, and brought together clinical and physiological research strands. But the winner doctrine, localizationism, contained strong diffusionist elements.

A remarkable difference between this book and the other aforementioned works is that Star focuses on scientific practice and on how two competing groups have deliberately contributed to posing hurdles to the other group’s practice. The phrenology literature offers different intellectual, social, individual, and collective approaches to the debate between phrenologists, but the focus always lies on what to do with the acquired knowledge (reforms, class struggle, or individual authority). Star, in contrast, focuses on how the knowledge is acquired, how findings are classified and standardized, how anomalies are explained, and how evidence from different fields is drawn together; though sometimes schematic, this is refreshing and seems appreciative towards her actors.

Michael Hagner’s “The Electrical Excitability of the Brain” is a revisionist account of histories of localization, for example, Young’s monograph. Instead of putting E. Hitzig and G. Fritsch’s experiment to electrically stimulate mammalian cortices in the context of the British and French localization movement that took off with P.P. Broca in 1861, Hagner argues that the experiment was born out of a practical clinical need. A close analysis of Hitzig’s publications and talks prior to 1870 leads Hagner to the conclusion that Hitzig was first and foremost a physician who used electrotherapy on his patients to relieve their pains and help them regain mobility in their limbs. According to Hagner’s reconstruction, Hitzig discovered muscle movements in an electrically stimulated patient only coincidentally and set out to design experiments to help him understand this artifact. Since he had not enough anatomical knowledge, he teamed up with Fritsch to help him design appropriate experiments that finally led to well-known result and publication about cortical excitability. Hagner emphasizes that a result like this was unthinkable within physiology, because the discipline firmly upheld the boundaries towards clinical medicine, anatomy, and pathology—and thus cortical localization. Physiological experiments were theory-driven and not intended to provide clinically useful results or anatomical knowledge, Hagner argues. Thus, Hitzig and Fritsch were not physiologists who provided useful knowledge for clinical applications; the reverse is true, according to Hagner. This also stands in direct contrast to Star’s work, who counts her “localizationists” to the physiologists.

More Book Summaries: Sex/Gender and Race in Genetics + Animals in the Lab and in the ‘Wild’

$
0
0

I just finished another set of readings for my orals list on “History of American Post-War Science and Feminism” with Susan Lindee. Read my summaries below and make sure to check out Etienne Benson’s site with many more resources on “wilderness” and STS.

Works Read
Eugenics, Sex/Gender, Race
Richardson, Sarah S. 2013. Sex Itself: The Search for Male and Female in the Human Genome. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Braun, Lundy. 2014.
Breathing Race into the Machine: The Surprising Career of the Spirometer from Plantation to Genetics. Minnesota: University of Minnesota Press.
Roberts, Dorothy E. 2011.
Fatal Invention: How Science, Politics, and Big Business Re-Create Race in the Twenty-First Century. New York: New Press.
TallBear, Kimberly. 2013.
Native American DNA: Tribal Belonging and the False Promise of Genetic Science. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

Animals, Anthropomorphism, Sex, and Evolution
Daston, Lorraine, and Gregg Mitman, eds. 2005.
Thinking with Animals: New Perspectives on Anthropomorphism. New York: Columbia University Press.
Zuk, Marlene. 2002.
Sexual Selections: What We Can and Can’t Learn about Sex from Animals. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Milam, Erika L. 2010.
Looking for a Few Good Males: Female Choice in Evolutionary Biology. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Haraway, Donna J. 1989. “Teddy Bear Patriarchy: Taxidermy in the Garden of Eden, New York City, 1908–36,” “Women’s Place Is in the Jungle,” and “Linda Marie Fedigan: Models for Intervention.” In
Primate Visions: Gender, Race, and Nature in the World of Modern Science. 26–58, 279–303, 316–30. New York: Routledge.
Fedigan, Linda M. 2001. “The Paradox of Feminist Primatology: The Goddess’s Discipline?” In
Feminism in Twentieth-Century Science, Technology, and Medicine, edited by Angela N. H. Creager, Elizabeth Lunbeck, and Londa L. Schiebinger, 46–72. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Logan, Cheryl A. 2001. “’[A]re Norway Rats … Things?’ Diversity Versus Generality in the Use of Albino Rats in Experiments on Development and Sexuality.”
Journal of the History of Biology 34 (2): 287–314. doi: 10.1023/A:1010398116188.
Pettit, Michael. 2012. “The Queer Life of a Lab Rat.”
History of Psychology 15 (3): 217–27. doi: 10.1037/a0027269.

Animals in the Lab and in the Wild
Clause, Bonnie T. 1993. “The Wistar Rat as a Right Choice: Establishing Mammalian Standards and the Ideal of a Standardized Mammal.”
Journal of the History of Biology 26 (2): 329–49. doi:10.1007/BF01061973.
Lynch, Michael E. 1988. “Sacrifice and the Transformation of the Animal Body into a Scientific Object: Laboratory Culture and Ritual Practice in the Neurosciences.”
Social Studies of Science 18 (2): 265–89. doi: 10.1177/030631288018002004.
Kohler, Robert E. 1994.
Lords of the Fly: Drosophila Genetics and the Experimental Life. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Benson, Etienne. 2010.
Wired Wilderness: Technologies of Tracking and the Making of Modern Wildlife. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

In her first monograph, historian and philosopher of science Sarah Richardson investigates into Sex Itself, that is, the ways in which cultural gender norms and stereotypes have shaped the search for sex differences in the genome in twentieth- and twenty-first-century genetics. The study is informed by a close reading of genetic, feminist, and popular texts as well as published interviews of geneticists. Richardson argues that the definition of X and Y chromosomes as “sex chromosomes” has “anchor[ed]” the cultural and scientific beliefs in a dichotomous sex (p. 2), even though various different interpretations of these chromosomes as well as maleness and femaleness have been proposed over the course of the twentieth century (chs. 2–4). Opposing geneticists argued that the term “sex chromosome” distorted the broader function of the X and Y chromosomes: the term was simplistic, could not be used across species, and did not illuminate the mechanism of the actual sexing of an individual at all. As Richardson shows, however, geneticists and popular voices of the 1910s and 1920s increasingly referred to “sex chromosomes” in order to promote a chromosomal version of hereditary science. In the 1930s and 1940s, the so-called “sex hormones” moved to center stage and “sex chromosomes” seemed the perfect genetic complement for a new science of sex that had been stabilized by the 1950s and 1960s, when genetics pushed to the forefront of the human sciences. But women were not passive. Richardson also shows (chs. 7 and 8) how feminism has shaped science through “direct exposure, osmosis, and demographic transformation” (p. 126).

Pathologist and STS scholar Lundy Braun’s first (!) book, Breathing Race into the Machine, traces the history of the spirometer, a device that quantifies lung function by measuring the volume of air exhaled by an individual. Invented in Victorian laboratories as a means to assess the lung function of British workers, the spirometer traveled the world and was still in use as a tool of evidence in asbestos lawsuits in the US at the turn of the twenty-first century, making it relatively hard for black workers to prove diminished lung function and obtain compensation. Braun’s account of the spirometer in Britain, the US, and South Africa illustrates how notions of race were literally built into these machines through a “race correction” switch; this materialized concept of race was mostly binary and always with ‘white’ individuals as superior (technically, regarding their lung function, but Braun shows—and we all know—that this is not what the ideology of white superiority was limited to).

Drawing on archival material, scientific publications, and interviews with and published information from spirometer manufacturers from the early to the later twentieth century, Braun shows how the ideology of racial inequality in the social and scientific realms traveled with the spirometer, which was sometimes used to assess the variance within ‘white’ populations (e.g., ch. 7) and sometimes to perform comparative studies across people of different skin colors (e.g., ch. 6). She illustrates that the spirometer of the mid-twentieth century was static in its built-in race “correction” but flexible, throughout the twentieth century, in its use for occupational safety, fitness movements, or racial discrimination—unfortunately always to the advantage of already privileged white male populations. Braun talks about sex/gender significantly more than Richardson mentions race (e.g., ch. 3); from Braun’s account, it becomes particularly clear that Sex Itself and Breathing Race into the Machine are similar proofs of the fact that covert cultural biases materialize in science and technology, be it through ascribing meaning to a chromosome or building a racist, sexist, and classist machine.

Fatal Invention is Dorothy Roberts’s third monograph, a four-part investigation into the ways in which racial categories have been created and used in public policy and biomedicine since the “invention” of race “as a system of governance and ‘moral apology’” during the years of slavery and westwards expansion in North America (p. 309). Drawing on a wide range of published historical and scientific literature as well as court cases, Roberts argues that the political origins of racial categories have been and are deliberately concealed in favor of a notion of biological differences between human races; biomedicine and molecular biology—genetics in particular—have served to stabilize, refine, surveil, and commercialize this political grouping, which today as in times of slavery provides an excuse for institutionalized economic, legal, educational, and health-related inequalities between individuals of different skin colors and ethnic backgrounds. Distinguishing between the deliberate abuse of racial categories, “scientific racism,” and the “reinforce[ment of] race,” which can occur in line with democratic interests (p. 27), Roberts illustrates that genetic explanations of race resonate very well with neoliberal biopolitics so aptly and yet uncritically described by Nikolas Rose; the responsibility and blame for not living the ‘American dream’ is ascribed to the individual and their biological heritage.

Just like Richardson, Roberts presents a clear political agenda in her works, but whereas Roberts makes her agenda explicit as a long personal fight from the first to the last page of her book, Richardson frames it in a more impersonal way as an intellectual proposition and policy implication—maybe because she believes that both gender and sex exists, whereas Roberts believes only in the political concept of race, not its biological substrate.

Kimberly TallBear joins the group of scholars for policy-relevance. She is a professor for Native Studies and a tribal citizen of the Sisseton-Wahpeton Oyate. Her first book, Native American DNA, illustrates the ways in which DNA testing to determine Native American heritage is redefining the notions of tribal belonging and challenges tribal governance. She draws on ethnographies, interviews, and published scholarship in feminism, Native Studies, and STS, was well as on textual analyses of advertisements, websites, and texts produced in internet communities; these sources allow her to show how DNA’s promise of scientific accuracy has replaced the importance of ‘blood’ in determining tribal heritage (ch. 1), how private DNA testing corporations commercialize Nativeness based on the very same promise (ch. 2), how self-identified non-Native individuals contribute to the commodification of “Native American DNA” by consuming DNA tests in the context of family tree research (ch. 3), and how the Genographic Project, aiming at mapping the movement of human populations, redefines racial and tribal identity in genetic terms in the tradition of colonial science (ch. 4).

This monograph ties in previously summarized accounts on the construction of human races (Roberts, Braun), on DNA profiling and the authority of the science of genetics (Comfort, Lindee, Duster, Lynch et al.), as well as the scholarship on feminist epistemologies (Richardson and section VII of this reading list) in that it makes visible the ways in which race and tribal belonging are simplified and essentialized, scientific uncertainties and inaccuracies are ignored, and folk knowledge as well as perceived identity are devalued.

The four parts of Lorraine Daston and Gregg Mitman’s edited volume Thinking with Animals treat human–animal relationships in historical and contemporary scientific laboratories, households, visual art, and other cultural contexts. The contributions of this edited volume elaborate the ways in which, on the one hand, humans have ascribed morality and intellectual capacities to animals and, on the other hand, have used animals as symbols and objects of as well as aid to their own reasoning, sometimes in rather schematic ways (e.g., chs. 4 and 5).

Part II of the volume contains a contribution by Elliott Sober, a chapter titled “Comparative Psychology Meets Evolutionary Biology: Morgan’s Canon and Cladistic Parsimony.” It discusses anthropodenial, the non-ascription of human characteristics to animals, and discusses the two different types of errors the approaches can produce. Sober illustrates that British psychologist and ethologist C.L. Morgan, studied in this essay, believed that humans are psychologically biased towards anthropomorphism. Morgan thus advocated for deliberate anthropodenial in his canon in order to evade the naïve anthropomorphism. Chapter five, Sandra D. Mitchell’s “Anthropomorphism and Cross-Species Modeling,” continues the study of the strong negative connotation of “anthropomorphism” in science, showing that the twentieth-century counter-movement of deliberately anthropomorphic cognitive ethologists and environmental ethicists is justified in the post-Darwinian insight into the close relatedness between all animals and useful as scientific models to be substantiated with empirical evidence.

Sexual Selections is a popular monograph written by the feminist biologist Marlene Zuk that provides insight into different forms of animal sexual behavior and debates the ways in which these insights relate to values and habits pertaining to human sexuality. Despite the fact that Zuk is criticizing her own profession, she analyses the extent to which stereotypical ideas held by scientists shape the allegedly objective studies of animal behavior and, in turn, how insights gained through biology influence the human understanding of sexual behavior and characteristics, sometimes too naively applied and leading to sexism, sometimes naturalizing socially sanctioned behavior, and in other cases bearing the potential to fuel sexual liberation movements. Zoomorphism and anthropomorphism are both debated, resonating well with Daston and Mitman’s edited volume; Zuk argues that animal studies targeting knowledge about ‘human nature’ are an epistemologically dangerous and ethically questionable undertaking. Furthermore, the discussion of reading gender stereotypes into sociobiological observations resonates perfectly well with Richardson’s account of gendering the so-called sex chromosomes.

Looking for a Few Good Males is another first book on this list. Erika Milam provides a study of sexual selection and the theory of the role of female choice of mating partners in evolutionary processes, illustrating that this topic has received considerable scientific attention since C. Darwin, even though the historiography argues that interest arose again only in response to R. Triver’s work on parental investment in the 1970s (the so-called “eclipse narrative”). Milam draws on archival collections on three continents, oral histories for which she conducted the interviews herself, contemporary biological journals, and scholarship from various fields. What is at stake with the concept of female choice, Milam shows, are, first, the delineation between the concepts of natural selection (“who survived”) and sexual selection (“who reproduced”) (p. 2); second, female agency; and, third, human exceptionalism.

Milam explains that diverse competing disciplines researching female choice originated from different disciplinary realms and employed various approaches and research sites—the lab and the field. Interestingly enough, the organismal biologists won out over molecular approaches, which is noteworthy in the face of the rise of genetics. But, as becomes clear, all of these approaches were similar in their attempts to utilize knowledge about non-human animals’ sexual behavior to extrapolate and evaluate human sexual behavior, a notion very familiar from Zuk’s monograph. The fact that Milam’s actors make their observations through a stereotypically gendered lens and employ both anthropomorphism and zoomorphism should not surprise, at least not after reading Richardson’s and Zuk’s works as well as Daston and Mitman’s edited volume.

In her second monograph Primate Visions, Donna Haraway analyses the narratives that originate from and within the field of primatology, focusing on notions of love, sex/gender, and nature/culture. Haraway illustrates that taxidermy, photography, and behavioral biology aim at detecting differences that are necessary to establish orders amongst individuals and species, an entirely political endeavor, she argues. In line with Zuk’s criticism of anthropomorphism and zoomorphism, Haraway contends that “western primatology has been about the construction of the self from the raw material of the other,” that is, the primate (p. 11). In doing so, scientists observe animals through a lens of stereotypes and presuppositions about humankind and the world. Further resonating with Zuk, Haraway identifies primatology as a field of highly “sexualized discourse” (p. 11). In the African Hall in the American Museum of Natural History, for instance, Carl Akeley and his two (consecutive) wives as well as many invisible African laborers have prepared specimens to create “a history of race, sex, and class” by carefully seeking out “’typical’” (p. 40), that is, “perfect” adult male (p. 41), animals to mount and tell a history of natural hierarchy and true manhood. “[O]rganicism” (p. 30), reproductive hierarchy, social hygiene, and preservation of decay became institutionalized in the African Hall, whose patrons were eugenicists and capitalist leaders of the country. Fittingly enough, the Second International Congress of Eugenics was held at the Museum in 1921.

In “The Paradox of Feminist Primatology,” Fedigan tackles the question of whether, as Haraway suggests in Part III of Primate Visions, primatology has become—or come close to being—a feminist science. In order to test this thesis, Fedigan applies Londa Schiebinger’s eight “Tools of Gender Analysis” (p. 48) to the history, knowledge, and methods of primatology. She gives a positive answer to each of the questions of whether primatology has increased the use of these eight tools in the past decades, with an exception of the fifth tool, “Gender Dynamics in the Cultures of Science.” Fedigan argues that primatology has developed “an androgynous culture” prior to the years of second-wave feminism, simply by good women’s entering the field and proving their adequacy. But despite all of the obviously feminism-influenced changes in the field of primatology, Fedigan argues that primatology has only benefited from “cultural assimilation” (p. 66) and not become a feminist field, because primatologists deliberately try to not be identified as feminists, fearing this may “feminize(d)” their discipline and cost them authority (p. 64), let them seem politically inclined instead of ‘objective’ and unbiased, or may even challenge their deeply ingrained positivistic view of science.

Cheryl Logan, an experimental psychologist turned historian of science, discusses another species of great importance to the study of animal sexual behavior in her paper “’[A]re Norway Rats … Things?’.” Tracing US-American and German-speaking research in behavioral biology from the late nineteenth century to 1930, Logan shows that researchers on both continents valued white rats for their studies for two major reasons: first, they developed slowly and allowed for directed interventions in experimental contexts, and, second, their sexual drive was considered to be very pronounced, an obviously desirable trait in studies of sexual behavior. Logan argues that the widespread use of rats as laboratory animals did not prevent researchers to think in comparative terms until 1915. Rats seemed to be convenient model organisms and thus one step in the direction of obtaining a much broader knowledge about sexuality in many species. By 1930, however, fueled by the rise of the experimental paradigm and the easy availability of industrially produced standardized Wistar Rats (see Clause’s paper below), the comparative focus was abandoned and this special kind of white rats came to be considered the organism for obtaining generalizable knowledge about animal, including human, sexuality, Logan argues.

STS scholar Michael Pettit’s article “The Queer Life of a Lab Rat” continues the analysis of rodents as subjects in studies pertaining to animal sexuality. Pettit’s article is framed by queer theory and draws on archival letters as well as published scientific literature. Pettit traces F. Beach’s research of the reversal of sexual behavior in laboratory rats in the 1930s and 1940s. Beach observed that males can exhibit “female” sexual behavior and females can exhibit “male” sexual behavior in situations of high sexual excitement or under the influence of hormonal treatment. In particular, Beach’s research suggested that the so-called sex hormones did not function as their name suggested. This mistitlement of the “sex hormones” resonates well with Richardson’s argument of the inadequacy of the name given to the “sex chromosomes.” Pettit also argues that much of Beach’s “violence” (p. 224) towards his lab animals stemmed from the attempt to secure his own heterosexual marriage (by reversing the female diurnal rhythm so he could work regular hours and spend more time with his partner) and to eradicate the typicalities of female reproductive behavior (e.g., sterilizing female rats to prevent pregnancy or introducing round cages so they were forced to mate with a male in the absence of any corners to hide and prevent being mounted).

“The Wistar Rat as a Right Choice” is the first publication of independent scholar Bonnie T. Clause. The text analyzes the goals behind the production of the Wistar Rat as a standardized research animal that was bread at the University of Pennsylvania from 1906 through the 1940s and is thus a complementary account to Logan’s paper about white Norway rats in different places. Drawing on archival sources at the Wistar Institute for Anatomy and Biology Library, Clause weaves together the investments and goals of three main characters into what ended up a trademarked product: newly hired director M.J. Greenman’s attempts to advance the Wistar Institute and make it serve ‘science’ more broadly, neuroanatomist H.D. Donaldson’s need to find a suitable organism for his investigations into the growth of the nervous system, and zoologist H.D. King’s effort to obtain genetic material to continue her inbreeding studies. The alienation of the laboratory rats from their Norway rat ancestors resembled a factory of selective (in(ter))breeding as a means of standardization and perfection (cf. Akeley’s taxidermic endeavors as described by Haraway). As Clause illustrates, Greenman deliberately modeled the rat colony on F.W. Taylor’s principles of “Shop Management,” to promote scientific standardization akin to chemical purity in anatomy and biology. The Wistar Press as well as Greenman in person informally advertised the Wistar Rat as an efficient organism for scientific study, resulting in the industrialized production of 11,000 rats in 1913, 3,000 of which were shipped to other laboratories.

As a complement to the illustration of the industrial production of rats, Michael E. Lynch considers the ritual killing of laboratory animals in his paper “Sacrifice and the Transformation of the Animal Body into a Scientific Object.” Lynch draws on his observations during ethnographies in the 1970s, observing the interaction and rhetoric of laboratory scientists working mainly with rats. He illustrates how the individual “naturalistic animal” that needs to be tamed and handled in the laboratory is transformed into an abstract “analytic animal,” a set of mathematized data, “ostensibly an artifact—a product of human intervention” (p. 269). Depending on the docility of the living animal and the usefulness of the data provided, animals are classified into “good” and “bad” after being “sacrificed” for the advance of scientific knowledge. One important precondition to being a “good” animal, Lynch shows, is being a standardized animal that leads to clean data without any artifacts of individuality, an observation that validates the concerns of Clause’s actors in the attempt to standardize rats.

Robert Kohler, a trained chemist, continues the story of the creation and dissemination of standardized laboratory animals from 1910 to 1940 with a study on Drosophila flies in his third book Lords of the Fly. This is a story of scientific practice, its material culture (consisting of standard fly, fly group, and the exchange network), as well as the “moral economy” (E.P. Thompson’s term) connecting the drosophilists, that is, the scientists values, rules, and regulations that structured their scientific work and the social hierarchies amongst them and defined the recognition that individual researchers were granted. Kohler focuses on the work and international network of geneticist T.H. Morgan and his students at Columbia University and later the California Institute of Technology (cf. tables of institutions in the appendix). Kohler’s primary sources are contemporary scientific publications and a wide range of archival collection.

Kohler argues that the Drosophila (particularly the D. melanogaster) became a lab technology around which scientific investigations were built once it worked in the way intended. But the flies are not passive in Kohler’s account; he endows them with agency, showing how, for example, Drosophila took over several of Morgan’s research lines due to its manifold mutants that allowed the use of the fly for diverse experiments, a quality that only revealed itself after the fly had been introduced to the laboratories for mundane reasons like money and convenience (ch. 2). Another example would be the distinct “moral economy” that had to be developed in fly groups where conflicts could not easily be avoided since most of the work was shared and entire labs worked on the same topic with the same population of animals, a situation that called for a high degree of communality (e.g., ch. 4). The in-built limitations of the Drosophila and the experimental system it was part of that led to decades of experimentation with interdisciplinary methods and finally the move from the standardized lab fly to collecting wild flies in the field and returning them to the lab can be understood in a similar context of animal agency (chs. 6, 7, and 8).

Wired Wilderness is Etienne Benson’s first book, in which he describes the development of radio tracking and telemetry for ‘wild’ animals (birds, grizzly bears, tigers, and maritime animals) from the late 1950s to the early 2000s. Benson draws on oral histories, news reports, and documents from numerous archives of scientific institutions and museums across the US (see “Essay on Sources,” pp. 237–242), locating his story in the borderlands of the histories of science, technology, environment, conservation movements, and the Cold War. He argues that the availability of surveillance technologies significantly impacted the methods and ideology of wildlife science; the biologists saw a chance to increase their claim for objectivity in observations, the field became endowed it with a Cold-War rhetoric, and it regularly centered around the founding and infrastructure of military agencies and corporations (particularly ch. 1). Benson also shows that radio tracking led to controversies of whether these technologies allowed for the monitoring of ‘natural’ habits of different species or only for the observation of a few individuals whose movements were potentially altered by the technology they were carrying with them. Epistemological questions arose and ideological concerns about letting technology steer science into new directions were voiced by wildlife scientists. Like the Wistar Rat and the Drosophila, tracking devices and knowledge were circulated internationally, even as far as to India and Nepal (ch. 3). In contrast to Kohler’s illustration of a closely-communicating mass of fly groups, however, Benson shows that the specificity of radio tracking techniques were kept rather secret—very Cold-War-ish. Leslie, Edwards, Abbate, Kay, and others have shown how Cold-War rhetoric and mentality has permeated science and technology. Benson shows that not even “wilderness” could escape this development, maybe precisely because it is not actually wild.

Book Summaries: Cold War Social Science, Gender Roles, and Reproduction

$
0
0

I have done many more readings. The following essay from my Cold War science and feminism list with Susan Lindee is already 1.5 months old and I can read faster and type more efficiently by now. As a colleague of mine, one year ahead of me in the same program, tells the grad student applicants who come in every Monday these days: If we were able to start over grad school with the knowledge and strategies we have now, we would need to get a hobby! We’d be so bored reading only four books a week.

Works Read:

Social Science and Institutions

Simpson, Christopher, ed. 1999. Universities and Empire: Money and Politics in the Social Sciences during the Cold War. New York: New Press.

Rohde, Joy. 2009. “Gray Matters: Social Scientists, Military Patronage, and Democracy in the Cold War.” The Journal of American History 96 (1): 99–122. doi:10.2307/27694733.

Solovey, Mark, and Hamilton Cravens. 2012. Cold War Social Science: Knowledge Production, Liberal Democracy, and Human Nature. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

Cold War Rationality

Amadae, Sonja M. 2003. Rationalizing Capitalist Democracy: The Cold War Origins of Rational Choice Liberalism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Erickson, Paul, Judy L. Klein, Lorraine Daston, Rebecca M. Lemov, Thomas Sturm, and Michael D. Gordin. 2013. How Reason Almost Lost Its Mind: The Strange Career of Cold War Rationality. Chicago, London: University of Chicago Press.

Gender Roles and Reproduction

Gilbert, James B. 2005. Men in the Middle: Searching for Masculinity in the 1950s. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Robertson, Stephen. 2001. “Separating the Men from the Boys: Masculinity, Psychosexual Development, and Sex Crime in the United States, 1930s–1960s.” Journal of the History of Medicine and Allied Sciences 56 (1): 3–35.

Vicedo, Marga. 2011. “The Social Nature of the Mother’s Tie to Her Child: John Bowlby’s Theory of Attachment in Post-War America.” British Journal for the History of Science 44 (3): 401–26. doi: 10.1017/S0007087411000318.

Clarke, Adele E. 1998. Disciplining Reproduction: Modernity, American Life Sciences, and “the Problems of Sex.” Berkeley: University of California Press.

Martin, Emily. 1987. The Woman in the Body: A Cultural Analysis of Reproduction. Boston: Beacon Press.

Christopher Simpson’s edited volume Universities and Empire resembles Stuart Leslie’s The Cold War and American Science in that the essays provide very clear accounts of the ways in which federal agencies, including defense and intelligence services, cooperated with private funding institutions and universities in financing and directing academic research. The essays trace these developments since after World War I, but focus on the Cold War era, during which these groups mingled to form an “academic national security complex,” as Simpson calls it (p. xx). Not only was the direction of researched influenced, the volume argues, but “’legitimate’ [and] ‘unreasonable’ points of view” were actively defined by the federal agencies and “tacitly accepted” by the social scientists during the Cold War years (p. xi). In other words, this supports Leslie’s view that the universities gave up their intellectual independence. They did not utilize government and private funding in the ways they saw fit, but they were oftentimes the passive part of the aforementioned complex, carrying out the work that was suggested by the military, intelligence agencies, and other state bodies. In particular, the volume illustrates that the social sciences gained much authority and trust in the early years of the Cold War and were considered tools no less important than the natural sciences—at least until the 1970s, when the US government shifted its focus from universities to think tanks and other private institutions (see Lawrence Soley’s contribution).

Allan Needell’s chapter on “Project Troy and the Cold War Annexation of the Social Sciences” in the years 1950/51 at MIT is an early example of the deliberate investments of the CIA in on-campus social research. The project was supposed to compile knowledge, define further research avenues, and suggest potential structures for future research on psychological and political warfare against communism throughout the world and to aid the consolidation of ‘freedom’ within US borders. One result was the institution of CENIS in 1952, the Center for International Studies at MIT, a model institution for future research on how to manipulate and control social groups within and outside of the US. Project Troy and CENIS have had significant effects on later cooperation between the natural and social sciences in the interest of national security.

Irene Gendzier spells out in some more detail the extent to which the social sciences were used to provide both “information and legitimation” during the Cold War (p. 57) in “Play It Again Sam,” a contribution unraveling the politics of and continuities in development studies from the 1950s to the 1990s. In a similar vein, Ellen Herman illustrates that Project Camelot was an early-1960s effort to predict and influence political developments in developing countries. Project Camelot was part of a much broader interdisciplinary effort “to translat[e] psychological and behavioral expertise directly into the language of foreign policy and military action” (p. 100), which the US practiced secretly for two decades after World War II, until it was exposed as a political scandal in 1965. Whereas Leslie’s contempt for military science funding may sometimes be exaggerated, examples like these of the state’s cooption of the social sciences to conceal and make more effective attempts of gaining political control over much of the globe may actually be ‘evil’ research.

Joy Rohde’s “Gray Matters” complements Simpson’s edited volume with an assessment of three individuals at the Special Operations Research Office (SORO) at the University of Washington in the 1950s and 1960s. Rohde illustrates by means of three case studies about the researchers E.H. DeLong, J.S. Mintz, and R. Boguslaw the different ways in which social scientists saw their own role and their research’s impact in a state-military-university research complex. The three chosen individuals were average SORO employees; based on archival research, Rohde presents the ethical and epistemological quandaries of the researchers, who believed partly in the neutrality of knowledge and the serving nature of the citizen to the state beyond personal responsibility (DeLong), partly in the political power of knowledge and thus the individual responsibility of the (social) scientist to provide only methodologically correct and ethically defensible research (Mintz), and partly that knowledge is political per se and that all research is at the same time social action (Boguslaw—who nevertheless was an avid researcher on Project Camelot). Eventually and somewhat surprisingly, Rohde argues that these negotiations on the shoreline between state interest and academic research may be better guarantees for participatory democracy than a rigid separation of academic and military/state research as seen since the privatization of this research in the 1970s, as mentioned before.

Mark Solovey and Hamilton Craven’s edited volume Cold War Social Science is yet another contribution to the state of social science research and organization during the early 25 years of the Cold War, before the processes described by Kelly Moore in Disrupting Science had major consequences for social science funding, in particular on university campuses. One of the main arguments of this collection is that “Cold War social science” existed with its most distinct features of “unmatched prestige and unprecedented autonomy,” as Theodore Porter phrases it in the Foreword (p. xiv). This is not to say, however, that the contributors argue for a break with pre-WWII traditions in the social sciences. In fact, several chapters emphasize a continuity in methods or questions over the course of the 20th century. Solovey explains in his introduction that “Cold War social science” is mainly a “useful concept” to address the mutual influences of social science, political goals, and national security concerns on one another. David Engerman’s contribution about the Harvard Refugee Interview Project (RIP, sic!) even concludes that “multiple versions and visions of social science in the Cold War” need to be recognized in order to allow for various ways in which researchers have interacted with government funding (p. 38).

Two of the four chapters in Part I, “Knowledge Production,” trace the development of new disciplines during the Cold War: future studies and linguistics, both highly interdisciplinary fields that were crucially shaped by quantitative analyses and computer technologies. These developments speak to the shift in methodological tool kits in the social sciences during these years and reiterate the importance of computers for various types of Cold War knowledge as seen in the works of Paul Edwards, Donald MacKenzie, Fred Turner, and Sejal Patel, to name only a few (see a previous essay).

The four chapters making up Part II are overwritten “Liberal Democracy.” Hunter Heyck’s chapter, “Producing Reason,” for instance, discusses the ways in which 20th-century research about rational choice moved away from the chooser during the Cold War and towards the choice; more specifically, the ONR and RAND funded investigations into methods for forcing individuals to choose like rational subjects by constructing limited choices for them or providing information technologies to support the decision-making process and produce decisions benefitting the stabilization of liberal democratic systems. Another chapter in the same part of the volume by Joy Rohde is a more detailed version of her aforementioned argument that the protest movements of the late 1960s and 1970s contributed to a transfer of national security and military research in private institutions, a process that worked against participatory democracy.

Part III, finally, contains chapters analyzing the engagement of social science with “Human Nature,” such as the origins of human factors research in cybernetics and Cold War technology as laid out by Edward Jones-Imhotep in his chapter “Maintaining Humans.” “[D]istrust” in humans as well as machines, Jones-Imhotep says, are at the core of this new science (p. 175). This contribution is a welcome complement to MacKenzie’s analysis of technology failures in Knowing Machines. The need to “maintain” humans also resonates with Nathan Ensmenger’s account of attempts to discipline ‘the programmer’ in The Computer Boys Take Over. The convergence of the political, the social, the technical, and the scientific during the Cold War is obvious.

Sonja Amadae was educated in the history and philosophy of science as well as in the history of political thought. Her first monograph Rationalizing Capitalist Democracy combines the topics of these fields by providing a history of the ideas and methods of rational choice liberalism research as it pertains to democratic governing. Amadae covers developments from Adam Smith to the end of the 20th century but focuses on the early post-WWII decades, providing a clear account of the ways in which the paradigm shaped the social sciences in the Cold War and how it interacted with political ideologies during these years. Her reason for engaging with earlier economic and rational choice theories is to show that rational choice liberalism was a novel development of the mid-20th century, yet inspired by Enlightenment ideas (Part III). Her sources are publications from philosophy, history, and political theory, mainly from the English-speaking world in the second half of the 20th century. They allow Amadae to provide, as she phrases it in her introduction, an account of “the defeat of Marxism by rational choice liberalism,” which she defines as “a philosophy of markets and democracy” deliberately drawn up to protect American political and economic values in the face of the ‘Red Scare’ (pp. 2 f). This monograph is a detailed complement to many of the contributions in Solovey and Cravens’ aforementioned volume.

Part I, titled “Rational Policy Analysis and the National Security State,” details the anchoring of the theory in Cold War thought through its roots in systems analysis at RAND. Amadae follows the paradigm from the assessment of superior aircrafts to the social sciences and into the world of public policy in the 1970s, explaining that its omnipresence was decisive enough to make it the primary tool for both predicting human choices or social decision making and aiding choices in the realm of government policy. The following part of the book discusses “revolutions” through which rational choice theory was championed and further developed within the social sciences in the post-WWII years (p. 11)—to a large part by scientists who were affiliated with the RAND Corporation. These revolutions comprise the formal proof that collective choices cannot be predicted on the basis of individual preferences (social choice theory, K.J. Arrow, ch. 2) public choice theorists’ direct attacks on socialism by providing scientific analyses with normative political outcomes in favor of individual gains and liberal policies (J.M. Buchanan and G. Tullock, ch. 3), and positive political theory, a mathematized science of politics that did not depend on case studies but promised a solid foundation for positivist analysis (W.H. Riker, ch. 4). This is the story of the “philosophical victory” of “capitalism and democracy … over Soviet communism and Marxism” (p. 12). Part IV of the book compiles late-20th-century theories of rational choice theory, illustrating that the concepts have become most pervasive in political and social thought and still characterize the social and political system of the US.

Paul Erickson et al.’s slim but dense monograph is another account of systems analysis and rational choice theory in the first 25 years of the Cold War. It complements Amadae’s more intellectual history well; quite similar to Amadae, the authors draw mainly from published sources, but in addition they have consulted select archival collections in London, Paris, and the US. Like Amadae, the authors put much emphasis on the novelty of Cold War rationality and its turn aside from human judgment and moral considerations towards mathematical formalism and rules in decision processes. This sets them apart from one of the overarching arguments in Solovey and Cravens’s edited volume, namely that there were significant continuities in the methods and concerns of the social sciences throughout the 20th century. Even though Erickson et al.’s goal is “to make the label ‘Cold War rationality stick,” they admit that it is not an actors’ category, since the proponents of this way of reasoning intended “to articulate a pure rationality, valid independently of the problems to which it was applied, and therefore also valid for everyone and always” (p. 2). In much more detail than Amadae, the authors tackle the question of what form of “irrationality” their actors defined their new rationality against, that is, what was supposed to be overcome by the new fusion of mathematics, statistics, and economic theory and what “rationality” during these early decades of the Cold War actually meant in more psychological terms.

In chapters 1 and 2, Erickson et al. provide a pre-history of arithmetic and mechanized calculation from the Enlightenment to the mid-20th century: rules of thumb became formalized algorithms and the Berlin Airlift contributed to the rise of computer-based economic rationalization, which was more an ideology than a technology-driven practice, the authors argue. In the main part of the book, the authors provide different examples for the ways in which the proponents of rationality tried to employ this framework in their scientific studies and in real-world contexts. One case study treats psychological attempts to allow the mind to rationally tackle the nuclear question by either “being aware of the limitations on rationality” and enacting conciliatory moves even if they are not reciprocated (C.E. Osgood) or “quarantin[e] irrational minds” (I. Janis) in order to not victimize a set of decision makers to irrational “groupthink” (p. 84; ch. 3). Chapter 4 turns to the rise of “situations” enable the study of social dynamics in artificially reduced environments in the behavioral sciences and chapter 5 traces the even more rigid reduction of decisions into variables in a matrix, for instance, in the prisoner’s dilemma, in which the (ir)rational grounds for “trust” were assessed in particular.

Finally, chapter 6 explores in more detail the impacts of the psychological concept of humans’ intrinsic irrationality in the form of research on heuristics and biases during the 1980s. The psychologists’ assertion that rational choice theory can be very well employed in formalized contexts but not necessarily in real-life scenarios involving humans eventually weakened the trust in the concept, the authors show. Nonetheless, as they explain in the Epilogue, the idea of limited rationality and the usefulness of rational choice theory in economics as well as the social and political sciences have stuck with the so-called Western world. But whereas Amadae argues that rational choice theory was an invention of the Cold War that outlived it, Erickson et al. describe the theory as one of the curiosities of Cold War ideology, which was to a large extent dismantled, and that, in fact, these decades were “extraordinarily strange … times” (p. 188).

Emeritus professor of history James Gilbert’s Men in the Middle is a revisionist account of the alleged masculinity crisis in the white middle-class US society of the 1950s. Gilbert argues that the response to the purported de-masculinization after World War II with its rising mass culture, consumerism, and the ideals of companionate spouses and families was much more diverse than historians have previously suggested in accounts of the bemoaned end of “John Wayne’s America” (p. 1). Drawing on published literature and archival papers of several of his actors, Gilbert’s essays provide the reader with individual case studies about men who interpreted, welcomed, or fought this reconceptualization of the sexes in different ways.

After a historiographical essay about the masculinity crisis, Gilbert analyzes D. Riesman’s 1950 publication The Lonely Crowd, a discussion of the advent of mass culture and consumerism since the late 19th century and the shifts in social relationships these have brought about (ch. 3). Gilbert explains that Riesman was honestly concerned about these developments and suggested more autonomy and a new form of individualism as a remedy for the loss of American masculinity. A.C. Spectorsky remodeled the Playboy for similar reasons—in order to introduce a specific form of masculinity into higher culture and promote this life-style amongst American males (ch. 9). On the other end of the spectrum, A. Kinsey and B. Graham used the alleged decline of stereotypical pre-War masculinity for their own gains: Kinsey tried to scientifically capture and support a sexual revolution (ch. 5) whereas Graham preached the end-time and tried to advertise the ‘masculine’ aspects of Christian conversion in order to gain more male followers for Protestant evangelism (ch. 6). Notwithstanding the range of his well-executed case studies, Gilbert’s assertion that “[t]here were and are many ‘1950s’” (p. 1) does not entice him to provide a case study analyzing the stance of someone besides the referenced well-known white middle-class males. He does not even provide a reason for why he chose not to. He simply notes that some individuals may not have perceived the changes as either a crisis or an opportunity to promote their own ideologies like Graham or Kinsey, but who “enjoyed companionship with their wives and children” (p. 221). I am quite certain that he pictured these families in white suburbia, too.

Stephen Robertson’s “Separating the Men from the Boys” connects Gilbert’s account of the alleged masculinity crisis in the 1950s with early-20th century concerns about sex crime and male immaturity. Drawing mainly on newspapers and periodicals, Robertson traces the debate around male sex offenders and the attempts to scientifically explain these in terms of psychosexual development in the first six decades of the 20th century. Robertson argues that it was not only psychiatry’s authority that turned the sex crime panic into a debate surrounding psychopathology, as other historians have suggested before him. Instead, he suggests, the success of the theory of psychosexual development rested on psychiatrists’ effective employment of the sex crime panic and the support of the media. In scientific accounts and the popular media, allegedly exaggerated ‘normal’ sexual behavior, that is, heterosexual rapes among adults, were clearly distinguished from offenses against children, which allegedly proved the sexual immaturity of the offender. The sooner were deemed to be the behavior of merely disinhibited sexually mature individuals whereas the latter were pronounced the deeds of curable psychopaths whose pathology derives from bad parenting (‘good’ parenting: “an adult male … to identify with, [no] overprotective mothering, and [no] … sexual encounters with adult men,” p. 4). As a result of these theories, offenses against adult women were marginalized, boys were considered in equal danger of sexual assault as girls, and mature masculinity was scientifically linked to heterosexual hebephilia that may be recovered through therapy. Similarly to Gilbert’s account, this was a discourse about white males. Black individuals were perceived as ‘naturally’ immature, which is why black sex offenders were deemed incurable. We know what Dorothy Roberts would have to say to this.

Marga Vicedo’s paper “The Social Nature of the Mother’s Tie to Her Child” continues the conversation about good parenting and the masculinity crisis towards the end of the ‘momism’ era, that is, in terms of maternal deprivation rather than the lack of a father figure or overprotective mothering. Vicedo traces the reception of E.J.M. Bowlby’s work in early Cold-War America based on parental advice literature, newspapers, periodicals, and Bowlby’s archival papers. Bowlby was a British psychoanalyst and psychiatrist who claimed that specific acts of love and attention from an animal’s mother are a biological need and that children’s psychological development is determined by their mothers’ interactions with them. Bowlby admitted vaguely that other caretakers could theoretically fulfill a similar role, but that this was highly unlikely. As Vicedo argues, his theory was deployed as a successful argument to tie mothers to their homes and to traditional values of parenting in post-war societies. The theory was developed entirely from the viewpoint of the child’s needs, not of society’s wants or the mother’s abilities, “exert[ing] an unusually strong emotional and moral demand on mothers” (p. 402), whose love did not seem enough for the child’s healthy development if she decided to work outside of the home. Here, just like in Robertson’s history of the idea of psychosexual development, the media took a crucial role in promoting this theory and elevating it to a moral compass for gender roles, even though there were scientific theories indicating the opposite of Bowlby’s research, which led him to switch from researching humans to non-human animals and hammer even more the “disinterested position of science” (p. 425). Let us consult Donna Haraway on this one.

Adele Clarke’s first monograph, Disciplining Reproduction, is a history of the reproductive sciences in the US with an agenda: among other noble social impacts, it is supposed to guide policy decisions pertaining to reproductive science and women’s health, Clarke states in her preface. But the book is not least a valuable resource for the historian—rich in detail, analysis, and conceptual framework. Besides published primary and secondary sources that are listed in the extensive bibliography, Clarke utilizes archival collections of major funding institutions like the Rockefeller Foundation, the Bureau of Social Hygiene, further academic institutions and individuals, as well as some published oral histories and her own interviews. An appendix provides the reader with convenient lists and tables related to the members and funding activities of the National Research Council Committee for Research in Problems of Sex (discussed in ch. 4).

Clarke approaches the reproductive sciences in the US through the lens of “social worlds and arenas” and tells their history from 1910–1963 as a contingent development full of negotiations between an interdisciplinary set of reproductive scientists (biomedical and agricultural scientists), philanthropic and industrial founders of their research, as well as birth control advocates—even though reproductive scientists long resisted applied research into birth control, focusing more on “basic” physiological and endocrinological matters. “Disciplining reproduction” is explained on two levels: (1) how the discipline formed and that this happened late compared to other biomedical and social sciences, due to the suppression for reasons of sustained “illegitimacy”; and (2) how reproducing bodies were controlled and normalized through the reproductive technoscience, for instance, in that the new “scientific” methods of birth control require professional consultation, a distinctly “modern” phenomenon—whereas post-modern reproductive science after 1963 is directed at transforming and enhancing bodies and reproduction, Clarke suggests.

Although Clarke mentions the fact that reproductive science was almost exclusively carried out by men in the period discussed, she does not attempt to explain the ways in which this shaped scientific and popular understandings of masculinity and femininity in ways that Haraway or even Gilbert do. Clarke’s argument that the reproductive sciences diverged from their funding institutions’ initial wish they may base their studies on the foundation of the social rather than natural sciences does not allow her to explicate the relationship between the history of the reproductive sciences and the aforementioned literature on Cold War social science either. But it implicitly resonates very well with Robertson’s illustration of attempts to combat the sex crime panic of the early 20th century with scientific studies about psychosexual development. Finally, the observation that eugenics built a “market” for reproductive science (ch. 2) speaks well to works about the science of heredity and its abuses discussed in previous essays; this reminds us that not even the history of eugenics can be captured in a morally black and white picture.

Emily Martin’s anthropological study The Woman in the Body complements the above-mentioned studies of scientific and media accounts of gender and parenting with first-hand accounts of how the objects of scientific attention perceive themselves and their role in these contexts. This monograph is a study of the reactions of women to mechanical and production-oriented metaphors surrounding the major female experiences of menstruation and childbirth, as well as the metaphorically failing factory that allegedly is menopause. Martin juxtaposes these accounts from biomedical textbooks with interviews she conducted with women of different social backgrounds (working and middle class) as well as skin color (black and white) in three different life stages: those who are of childbearing age, those who are raising children, and those who are in or beyond menopause. Information in the appendices details the interview questions and provides short biographical sketches of all of the 165 female interviewees.

Martin conceives of science as a Gramscian hegemonic system and argues that men and women alike experience a “fragmentation of the unity of the person” (p. 19) in contemporary scientific contexts, but that the field, knowledge, and authority of the biomedical sciences themselves are much less accessible to women than to men, leading to an asymmetry between the men who are assessing bodies and the women within them. Female labor must be effective and the scientists and doctors oversee and control this Marxian production. Resistance to male ascriptions and societal expectations, Martin argues, occurs deliberately as well as subconsciously, for instance, in form the premenstrual syndrome as a way of opposing the industrial system of time and refusing the role of the keeper of familial harmony. Martin concludes that all women display similar levels of ”consciousness and resistance” (p. 201) when faced with scientific knowledge and societal expectations about their bodies and selves, regardless of their class or skin color, even though their perception of individual experiences and their form of resistance may differ. This similar attitude of “questioning, opposing, resisting, rejecting, and reformulating the ways in which they live and the ways in which the society might work” (p. 195), Martin argues, derives from the shared female experience of being primarily housekeepers and nurturers, roles in which they have been pushed by society, including science and the media, in ways that Gilbert, Robertson, and Vicedo have partly illustrated as well.

More Book Summaries on European History—and How These Relate to My Proposed Dissertation

$
0
0

The book summaries below are from my European History list with Heidi Voskuhl, a subsection titled “Bodies and Sexuality.” Since reading towards oral exams is not (only) an initiation rite, but also supposed to prepare me for my dissertation, I thought I’d post my current dissertation abstract before I provide the reading summaries. After all, hypotheses.org is for project-related blogs, not blogs of individual scholars. And this IS a project! Five to six years in grad school in preparation for this dissertation:

My dissertation traces and compares handedness and sex/gender as categories in the mind and brain sciences in Europe and the United States since the late nineteenth century. I inquire into the extent to which sex/gender and handedness were treated as unchangeable, innate qualities that originate from and impact the brain and mind. I also examine the interaction of changing conceptualizations of handedness and sex/gender on views of brains, selves, and groups of individuals sharing these characteristics. Particular attention is paid to the ways in which changes in scientific institutions and in society at large altered the understanding of the two categories. My work thus contributes to the historical scholarship on scientific classifications in different contexts: scientific laboratories, public policies, as well as social and cultural life more broadly. Since handedness has been largely neglected by historians, scientific publications as well as archival collections are crucial to this project. Combining close reading with large-scale digital text analyses will illuminate the practice and impact of scientific classifications. The dissertation will thus draw awareness to the continuities and ruptures in the meanings of two of the most pervasive categories in contemporary societies and to the relations between them.

Now you know what I’m talking about when I make statements about the ways in which these readings relate to my prospective dissertation topic (as I try to do more and more, as you will see even better in later and not-yet-posted essays).

Works Read:

Hunt, Margaret R. 2010. Women in Eighteenth-Century Europe. Harlow: Pearson Education.

Abrams, Lynn. 2002. The Making of Modern Woman: Europe 1789–1918. Longman History of European Women 5. Edinburgh, London: Pearson Education.

Scott, Joan W. 1996. Only Paradoxes to Offer: French Feminists and the Rights of Man. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Roberts, Mary L. 2002. Disruptive Acts: The New Woman in Fin-de-Siècle France. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

Allen, Ann T. 1991. Feminism and Motherhood in Germany, 1800–1914. New Brunswick/New Jersey: Rutgers University Press.

Wildenthal, Lora. 2001. German Women for Empire, 1884–1945. Durham: Duke University Press.

Hau, Michael. 2003. The Cult of Health and Beauty in Germany: A Social History, 1890–1930. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

Surkis, Judith. 2006. Sexing the Citizen: Morality and Masculinity in France, 1870–1920. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

Mosse, George L. 1996. The Image of Man: The Creation of Modern Masculinity. New York: Oxford University Press.

Hull, Isabel V. 1996. Sexuality, State, and Civil Society in Germany, 1700–1815. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

Gallagher, Catherine, and Thomas W. Laqueur, eds. 1987. The Making of the Modern Body: Sexuality and Society in the Nineteenth Century. Berkeley: University of California Press.

Matysik, Tracie. 2008. Reforming the Moral Subject: Ethics and Sexuality in Central Europe, 1890–1930. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

Spector, Scott, Helmut Puff, and Dagmar Herzog, eds. 2012. After the History of Sexuality: German Genealogies with and beyond Foucault. Spektrum 5. New York: Berghahn Books.

Women in Eighteenth-Century Europe is Margaret Hunt’s truly pan-European inquiry, as the list of consulted libraries in the acknowledgements suggests. The treatment of “Ottoman women” (or ‘Ottowomen’?) as European citizens in particular, Hunt explains in her introduction, needed some long neglected elaboration (p. 2). Hunt’s bibliographical references point mostly to 20th– and 21st-century secondary sources, but boxes with lengthy excerpts of “Voices from the Past” (e.g., p. 32) and not least Hunt’s recommendations for “Further Reading” towards the end of the book reveal a solid engagement with primary sources as well. A big concern regarding all groups of women treated is Hunt’s question of whether or not they “possessed historical agency” (p. 5). Her answer is ‘yes’, but she also names some caveats: the absence of written records on many forms of female resistance, historians’ bias to acknowledge only several forms of agency as such (e.g., not the one acted out in the religious realm), and the problem of acknowledging ways of agency that were enacted at the expense of other—and weaker—women, without concerns about female solidarity.

Hunt’s work is a much needed complement to accounts in the style of Nipperdey’s and Wehler’s male-centered histories, but it covers much more geographical ground and can thus not give as much detail as Nipperdey and Wehler can, even though Hunt also treats a much shorter period of time than her old male colleagues. The topics she discusses have much resemblance to Wehler’s chapter structure. It is remarkable that Hunt chose to offer a compilation of women’s concerns in the 18th century rather than a coherent argument that is contextualized with political and social changes, with the exception of maybe the chapter on revolutions that ties in women’s marginalization and political developments. One of the bigger arguments the book does make is certainly that there was much overlap between central and eastern European countries as well as the traditions in the Ottoman Empire and that any ‘othering’ was mainly a rhetoric device of contemporary actors asserting the “West’s” superiority.

Several ‘small’ arguments connect the individual chapters of the monograph. For instance, Hunt identifies both literacy and (an increase of) sexual freedom as intellectually and emotionally liberating as well as beneficial to women’s health and wellbeing more broadly (chs. 3 and 7). Furthermore, she illustrates that women’s living situations did not steadily improve over the course of the 18th century; for instance, food and the general living standards were significantly disrupted by the revolutions in the late 18th century, and the industrial revolution did not immediately lead to more economical power or at least equality either (chs. 4, 5, and 9). As far as women’s rights go, Hunt shows that feminist demands were starting to be fulfilled only after the Napoleonic era (i.e., after 1815), and she asks if, assuming central European women had known of the property rights of their Muslim neighbors, for instance, some forms of emancipation would have taken that long (chs. 3, 8, and 9). Eventually, Hunt concludes that “if the story of eighteenth-century women teaches us anything it is that the outcome of collective interventions is often very difficult to predict, either in the short or long range” (p. 381), that is, the history of women is as contingent and unpredictable as political history as Blackbourn and Eley, amongst others, remind us.

Lynn Abrams’s The Making of Modern Woman takes up women’s history where Hunt left off and tells the history of European women in the long 19th century, from the French Revolution to the end of WWI. Abrams covers similar topics as Hunt, even though her focus lies more on social factors than on cultural developments; in addition, Abrams does not extend her “Europe” to the Ottoman Empire and “Europe” seems to be mostly coherent whole, which is surprising since Sheehan already emphasized the huge varieties across the German states alone (see last essay). Furthermore, Abrams’s main contribution is to compile secondary sources with regard to women’s experiences in three fields: their roles and ascriptions to their bodies and personalities, their lives in families and the workplace, as well as their experiences in the political realm during colonization, first-wave feminism, the finally successful fight for women’s suffrage, and the Great War. The contemporary sources Abrams refers to are mostly derived from present-day editions of primary sources. The big overlap between Hunt’s and Abrams’s works as well as the German histories of Nipperdey and Wehler is the topic-oriented organization that breaks up traditional periodization and better reflects the continuities (considered “female,” pp. 4 ff) and ruptures (considered “male”) in 19th-century history and in women’s experiences.

Abrams reminds us that the course of history did not necessarily mean an improved standing of women. For example, with the Enlightenment in the late 18th century came new views of the female body and the feminine role in society; the nature-culture divide was formulated scientifically with all of its religious, political, and social implications, that is, biology was seen as a determinant of one’s personality and one’s membership of the alleged separate social spheres or men and women (ch. 1). How to acquire the proper femininity and inhabit the female sphere, that is, the non-intellectual realms and the home as a reproducer and nurturer, was taught to girls and women in their own families and marriages, in formal education, in books, in periodicals, and through serving professions (chs. 2, 4, and 5). Nonetheless, the patriarchal power of marriage decreased over the course of the 19th century, when love marriage became more common amongst the European middle classes and when the (re-)institution of relatively liberal divorce laws made it easier for women to live a self-determined life (ch. 3). Not only divorce, but also remaining an unmarried widow and continuing the inherited business or running a home according to her own principles were further ways of resistance against the very pervasive role models (chs. 3 and 5).

Moreover, Abrams illustrates the ways in which women took the first steps towards sexual liberation pertaining to their own pleasure, choice of sexual partners, or birth control and argues that these developments were the stepping stone towards a much broader female emancipation in the social and political realms (ch. 6). With regard to professional occupation, women’s options remained very limited until well into the 20th century (ch. 7); similarly most European women had to wait until the end of WWI to gain suffrage (ch. 8). But feminist movements in Europe (ch. 10) and its colonies (ch. 9) finally led to significant improvements in women’s lives, from education to employment to citizen rights and moral standing. Abrams ends her considerations with women’s work for and fighting in WWI, asserting that it further disrupted the old Enlightenment gender roles but could not entirely dismantle them (ch. 11).

Abrams’s concise account serves as a first overview that elicits many questions for more specific information and personal stories of women in different places. Just like Hunt’s work, it also leaves the reader with the question of why so few of the white men in the previous section of this orals list (see last essay) have at all—and if, then to a marginal extent—engaged with women. Furthermore, Hunt’s and Abrams’s attention to women did not include substantial considerations of children and their status in society, neither boys nor girls. We know from Wehler’s and Nipperdey’s accounts of Germany that ‘adolescence’ was invented as a concept in the 19th century and treated as a distinct societal challenge; Abrams at least could have expanded on this issue.

Joan Scott details the history of long-19th-century feminism with her monograph Only Paradoxes to Offer. The work provides the reader with case studies of individual female French feminists in chronological order, showing that the question of whether the argument of differences or similarities between men and women makes for a more successful or morally ‘better’ feminism is misleading. In her own words, Scott argues “that feminist agency is paradoxical in its expression” in that its emphasis on individualism oftentimes strengthened arguments for the oppression of females based on notions of sex differences (p. 16). Furthermore, Scott means to explicate “that feminist agency has a history,” or in other words, that “it is an effect of ambiguities, inconsistencies, contradictions within particular epistemologies” (ibid.). In doing so, Scott illustrates the extent to which not even the concepts of “woman” and “feminism” remained constant over the course of the century, let alone any value judgement of the ways in which women fought for civil rights, social liberties, and cultural freedom.

Scott draws mainly on published primary and secondary sources. In chapter 2, she introduces her first case study on Olympe de Gouges, who published a Declaration of the Rights of Woman and Citizen in 1791. Scott explains the ways in which de Gouges’s call for women’s rights rested on her assertion of specific female qualities that made women eligible as full citizens and at the same time her tendency to represent women (including herself) as men in this fight for rights as “active citizens” (pp. 33 ff). With an even stronger ideological foundation than de Gouges, Jeanne Deroin subscribed to heterosexuality and the differences between the alleged two sexes on the foundation of a Saint-Simonian mindset of the couple, not the individual, as the core unit of society (ch. 3). Deroin invoked a rhetoric of complementarity and the ability to bear and rear children as the reason for women’s equal value and her socialist demands for suffrage and working rights in the revolutions of 1848. Hubertine Auclert, identifying with socialist and republican values as the two movements grew apart, was one of the major figures to fight for women suffrage in the Third Republic. Like Deroin and de Gouge, Scott shows, she invoked women’s unique characteristics, like maternalism and socialist interests, in order to advocate for women’s political rights (ch. 4).

Madeleine Pelletier did not support any argument that invoked sex differences as a reason for female liberation (ch. 5). To her, equal rights were the means to escape femininity and subjective femaleness, which she called “psychological sex,” a concept that resembles our idea of ‘gender’ (p. 134). Her denial of her body’s power to make her feminine that she proved in her writing and cross-dressing, for instance, led authorities to refer to her as a lesbian while she herself reported to be celibate and seems to not have abandoned the idea of homosexuality’s being an abnormality. Pelletier derived her strong convictions from observations of the egalitarian play among children and her knowledge as a psychiatrist and physician—a combination of characteristics that makes her highly attractive for my dissertation as an early-20th-century professional on brain sex differences and feminist activist. The entire monograph is intriguing and of outmost conceptual importance regarding the variability of ‘feminism’ over the course of the 19th century, but Pelletier’s case study is probably the only one of direct relevance to my dissertation project.

In Disruptive Acts, Mary Roberts provides more case studies of women resisting the pressures of misogyny and sexism in late-19th and early-20th century France (most prominently, newspaper founder and actress Marguerite Durand, actress Sarah Bernhardt, and writers Gyp and Séverine). Similar to the ‘masculinity crisis’ in the post-WWII US (see James Gilbert’s Men in the Middle, not on this list), fin-de-siècle France partially fought and partially embraced a disintegration of Third-Republic liberal values and gender roles, leading to the emergence of the “New Woman,” perceived as a threat to both femininity and masculinity. Unlike Allen’s maternal feminists (see below), which also existed in France at the time, Roberts’s New Woman was the working woman, the feminist activist, the single woman, the wife in an untraditional marriage, or another type of publicly visible and scrutinized dangerous woman that escaped or parodied the traditional domestic sphere and entered the public sphere as a (non-)mother out of choice rather than natural law (the “public sphere” is a topic familiar from Wehler’s and Nipperdey’s German histories and to elaborated on in more detail by Allen).

Roberts draws on archival material, newspapers, and periodicals to investigate into the question of how this escape from the traditional domestic female was possible for these women and how the viewed themselves. “[A]cting and acting up” (ch. 2), physically leaving the domestic sphere and appearing in public, performance and revaluations of traditional roles and behaviors, entrepreneurial spirit and bravery, employing the press as a political medium, posing as eccentric stars and creating spectacle (ch. 6), consuming and offering themselves as commodities (ch. 7), as well as seduction, narcissism, and mimicry (ch. 3) are all possible answers to this question. Roberts does not romanticize her main characters and makes clear the extent to which they fought their own disenfranchisement without empathy for other oppressed groups, a theme familiar from Hunt’s account, as becomes clear in Gyp’s anti-Judaist nationalism (ch. 5). This is particularly remarkable since the New Woman and the Jew got increasingly linked in the nationalist imagination around 1900, Roberts shows—very concretely, through “Dreyfusardism” and being Jewish (Bernhardt), or more ideologically by associations with decadence and degeneration (ch. 4).

Roberts’s choice of individuals in the realm of theater and journalism is no coincidence. Roberts argues that these were, in their economic marginality, the most progressive communities of their time and thus provides a vivid picture of how the social and cultural histories of France—and women—are and can be written as closely intertwined. Consequently, this is yet another book about middle-class women—Scott, Allen, Wildenthal, and Hau (see below) also follow female characters whose overwhelming majority originates from the middle class(es). It is interesting to see the wide variety of concerns and strategies in French and German middle-class individuals, but it is at the same time a shame that quieter feminists’ voices are not recovered (see Hunt above).

German Women for Empire, 1884–1945 is Lora Wildenthal’s history of women’s involvement in German colonialism during the first decades of unified Germany through the end of WWII. The array of sources consulted is vast: archival papers from state agencies, missionary organizations, women’s associations, nursing institutions, and relevant individuals as well as periodicals and other published primary and secondary sources—including works of fiction—as detailed in long bibliographical lists. The appendix contains furthermore a short but very helpful list of “Colonialist and Women’s Organizations.”

In five chapters, Wildenthal illustrates the ways in which women of the late 19th and early 20th century have convinced men of their importance in building the German empire and how they have managed to institutionalize their support of German colonialism even before the achievement of women’s suffrage, for instance, as secular nurses (ch. 1), independent planters and writers (ch. 2), potential wives that would stop the “race mixing” (p. 5) of the early years of colonialism (ch. 3), farmer-settlers (including feminists advocating spiritual motherhood as defined by Allen; ch. 4), and sustainers of German-ness in former colonies after they had been freed from German rule as well as proponents of National Socialists ideologies of so-called racial purity (ch. 5). Throughout her book, Wildenthal emphasizes the diversity of these women regarding their religious, political, or geographical backgrounds. A crucial commonality is obvious: neither of these women could ever escape their metaphorically or literally reproductive and nurturing role. Wildenthal further makes clear that the mindsets over the course of the history she writes are diverse; even though the colonialist organizations and concerns survived until the Nazi regime, Wildenthal emphasizes that the colonizers’ attitude is not the same racism as the mid-20th-century anti-Judaism.

Wildenthal also discusses masculinity, for instance in a chapter about German’s sexual relations with colonial women and intermarriage (ch. 3). She shows that political confrontations between early conservative colonizers and later liberal nationalist colonizers subsumed the question of the freedom of marriage for colonizing men. In another vein, colonialist masculinity was again tied to the absence of German women in the colonies, Wildenthal argues. Some of the male colonizers deliberately sought patriarchal or even abusive relationships with colonial women that were not tolerated in Germany. The colonizing women, Wildenthal shows, both overtly criticized and covertly supported these practices—by not asserting the equality of colonized women with themselves in fear of losing the authoritative status they had fought for so deliberately. This female or even feminist assertiveness at the expense of other, underprivileged, women is a familiar trope from Hunt’s work on European women. Apart from this parallel, although the forms of nationalism and racism displayed in Wildenthal’s work seem so crucial to the German identity after the unification, none of the other authors on European women’s history on this list elaborates on it.

The Cult of Health and Beauty in Germany is another contribution to unraveling German-ness in the late 19th and early 20th century. Michael Hau draws on a wide array of contemporary periodicals, newspapers, health advice literature, and propaganda, as well as on select archival sources, including visual material, in order to illustrate an alleged German obsession pertaining to hygiene, fitness, and good looks in the form of popular knowledge that sometimes competed with conventional medicine: the buergerliche life reform movement, associated with nudism, vegetarianism, and natural therapies. Hau uses frameworks from Mikhail Bakhtin and Pierre Bourdieu to explain individual interpretations of shared social conditions to argue that the experience of this “cult” was distinct according to one’s social background. Here, he focuses on antagonisms within the German middle class, the different strata of the Buergertum so aptly described by Wehler.

This is a history of medicine as well as it is a German history. Hau includes the rise of the medicalization of health and beauty in the Wilhelmine period (chs. 1–5), arguing that taking charge of one’s (in particular men’s) health in scientific terms was a way of regaining agency in an industrializing society with its economic pressures, professional expectations, and an increasingly sedentary life style. The fitness movement was also an overt protest against conservative intellectualism and elitism—even though the aesthetic ideal was borrowed from Greek antiquity.

Hau emphasizes the racialized ideals of beauty around the transition from the German Empire to the Weimar Republic (chs. 6–8), linking his observations to early-20th-century public hygiene and eugenics. Other than Wildenthal, who makes clear that German colonialism did not lay the necessary foundations for the National Socialist catastrophe, Hau tries to show that the roots of Nazi racism are closely tied to turn-of-the-century concerns surrounding health and beauty. But he does so in a highly contextualized manner, for example, in that he explains the necessity of a holistic constitution-based view of body and character, or explains why nudist culture was supposed to end all class but not race distinctions, or links the contempt for “exotic” and lower-class women (p. 5) with contemporary notions of female chastity and rigid gender roles in the face of feminist demands for change. One big difference that Hau identifies between the Nazi ideology and the earlier “cult” is the violent propaganda against static groups of people whereas the ideal in the decades prior to 1933 was “always publicly contested and rarely stable” (p. 8).

It is particularly remarkable that Hau does not forget to talk about the need to assert masculinity against women or individuals from different classes. Race, class, and gender are bound together very well in this study, resonating with the works of Abrams, Allen, and Wildenthal, and making Hau’s social approach to the question of health and beauty very convincing. Furthermore, Hau provides a valuable counterpart to Scott’s ‘paradoxical’ study in that he not only shows how feminists and anti-feminists used the same metaphors but also that class antagonism can radically change the meaning of the same phrase or aesthetic figure, apparently to the extent that it can be fortified and employed to serve the stabilization of a cruel dictatorship.

Judith Surkis’s monograph Sexing the Citizen expands on the topic of masculinity and includes adult men as well as adolescents; a social group defined in the 19th century according to Wehler and Nipperdey, and a matter of concern that Abrams’ account, for example, falls short of. With a similar periodization as Hau, Surkis traces the deliberate “sexing” of male French (and Algerian) citizens by philosophers, sociologists, and policy makers through the early decades of the Third Republic. She illustrates that actively exerting one’s political rights became redefined as not only a republican privilege or obligation but a crucial aspect of masculinity. This sexing of the male with full citizen rights and the female (and child and solider) without was a stable ground on which authorities further advocated for monogamous heterosexual marriage, in order to stabilize the new masculinity in the social realm. In addition, marriage policies were a means of containing male sexuality that was considered “a locus of specific social and political problems” (p. 5; ch. II). Furthermore, Surkis analyzes Emile Durkheim’s argument that conjugal marriage is one of the crucial characteristics of modernity, or at last modern masculinity (Part III). The “public” and the “private spheres” are successfully deconstructed (see Hull’s contradictory argument below).

Surkis draws from a variety of contemporary periodicals and other published primary sources. Her main argument is that the “sexing” of citizens was a sometimes incoherent process that established “sex,” an entity that does, and here she is in line with Michel Foucault, not precede the authorities’ attempts to regulate citizens’ societal roles and sexual behaviors. Like Abrams has shown for European femininity in the same period, Third-Republican masculinity is something that needed to be taught and learnt, for instance, by means of moral education for children (Part I), marriage statistics, sociological assertions of the value of families (Parts II and III), and medical threats of venereal disease (Part IV). Surkis shows that men’s belief in the necessity of heterosexual monogamy and prescribed masculinity as the pillars of the French society was firm, even though individuals occasionally violated these norms; as a result, demographers intervened against bachelorism and sexual deviance was defined as sexual pathology (Part II). Surkis’s assertion of the authorities’ eagerness to police transgressions like these seems particularly logical when read alongside Wildenthal’s account of the threat of the New Woman during these very years.

Anachronistically speaking, George Mosse tied in the accounts of Roberts, Hau, and Surkis in The Image of Man. “Anachronistically speaking,” because it was published up to a decade before any of the three books whose topics it touches upon in explaining the rise of a new and lasting ideal of masculinity from the late 18th century through after WWII. Mosse argues that the new masculinity was a distinctly modern invention, a man-fashioning after absolutism that drew from the aesthetics of ancient Greek infused with conservative ideals of chivalry: strength, balance, morality, and honor. Instead of following on-the-ground negotiations surrounding individual thinkers and concrete campaigns to draw up and stabilize the new image of masculinity in circumscribed spaces, like Surkis does, Mosse directs his spotlight on several locations in the bigger-picture intellectual history of the “(stereo)type” of masculinity that was produced in the most influential states of Europe by a few privileged men (physicians, philosophers, politicians, and the churches). In accordance with Hau, Mosse shows the importance of concepts of holistic health and beauty of a person as well as the racialization and feminization of imperfection or “the countertype” (chs. 4 and 8). He does not, however, provide a detailed analysis of the distinctive appropriation of the new ideal by different sectors of the middle classes in the 19th century. But he illustrates the extent to which the New Woman in the late 19th century, as explained by Roberts, increased the demands for a strong positive masculine stereotype as a conservative counterbalance (ch. 5).

Mosse drew mostly on contemporary fiction, the popular press, and propaganda material as well as on select medical and scientific sources. The account proceeds chronologically. In chapter 2, Mosse argues that the new ideal of manhood was formulated in the second half of the 18th century and found its proponents in philosophy as well as physiognomic and phrenological ideas of harmonious body-character relationships. The “Aryan” type, as already laid out by Hau, fit and young, was the new ideal against which the “type” man was measured, Mosse argues. Curiously enough, the same stereotype was shared by the European states that Mosse described and yet connected to patriotic nationalism for only one’s own home country, an attitude that was even strengthened during wars (chs. 3 and 6). A related ideal type, just with less emphasis on beauty than on strength, was even upheld by socialists (ch. 6). Most performative was the notion of “getting there,” that is, individuals’ belief that self-shaping would lead oneself closer to the ideal, for instance, by doing gymnastics, maturing intellectually, abstaining from sexual deviance, and avoiding all forms of “decadence” (chs. 2 and 5). Mosse shows that neither the bare warrior nor the socialist worker types succeeded in replacing the traditional 18th-century image of masculinity that was unprecedentedly strong in the interwar years, stabilized by formal education, boy scouts, adventure novels, clubs and associations, etc. (ch. 7).

Mosse offers a new interpretation for the Shoah (ch. 8). Tracing the ideal of masculinity to fascism in Italy as well as in Germany, and even going as far as to suggest that “the clean-cut Englishman, the all-American boy, and the ideal member of the SS … shared essentially the same masculine stereotype,” Mosse argues against a teleological history of masculinity that culminates in the mass murders of WWII (p. 180). He argues that fascism and racism overemphasized the warrior aspects of the traditional ideal and that “racism brutalized them and transformed theory and rhetoric into reality” (p. 180). But when the fascist “new man” died after WWII, ideal masculinity, “clean-cut and fit” (p. 181), lived on in the media and in the European imagination (ch. 9).

Sexuality, State, and Civil Society in Germany, 1700–1815 is Isabel Hull’s complement of Hunt’s women’s history in 18th-century Europe, detailing the experiences of women and men in Germany as it transitioned from absolutism to a modern state. Hull focuses on the construction of and instruction in sexuality as a state-building measure, the “sexual system,” as she calls it, that is, “the patterned ways in which sexual behavior is shaped and given meaning through institutions” (p. 1). She concerns herself with the construction of modern sexuality—or heteronormativity—by the state and by civil society, two separate spheres by the early 19th century, she argues. Hull makes similar observations as Foucault regarding the permeation of society and state with sexual concerns, but her argument is grounded in an assessment of a wide array of published primary sources as well as archival research, allowing Hull to gain insight into developments in Baden-Baden, Baden-Durlach, Bavaria, Hamburg, and Prussia from 1600 to 1848.

Similar to Abrams’s, Scott’s, and Allen’s concerns, Hull invests lots of energy in assessing the structuring power of dichotomies like public (male) vs. private (female). She argues that the “social disciplining” of the absolutist state permeated every aspect of human life but not the “private sphere”—since this concept did not even exist before the 18th century was well underway (ch. 2). Even when reformers attempted to alleviate coercive punishment for alleged sexual misbehavior and to introduce incentives for moral behavior instead in the late 18th century, the argument that the state should not invite the citizens’ private life was hardly an official concern (ch. 3). This changed with the rise of the cameralists, who held the opinion that the state should not get involved with private matters that can be just as well regulated by an appeal to morality; an obligation to contribute to the common good was the key teaching for the new civil society (ch. 4).

“The practitioners of civil society,” that is, privileged men, started voicing their concerns about the state and society as individuals or collectives in the late 18th century and were gradually acknowledged by the rulers as a sphere separate from the state apparatus (ch. 5). The Enlightenment civil society was conventional in its values—including the belief in deadly sins—and concerned itself with sexual morals as well as debates about gender and the role of women and the extent to which these challenged the freedom of civil society (chs. 6 and 7). Some studies of females grew out of a new appreciation for sex/gender differences; however, Hull explains, “speculation about women was merely a function of the more fundamental task of defining men” (p. 225). The contemporary notion that the repression of the sexual drive until marriage and its heterosexual (re)orientation are intrinsically linked with citizenship and civil rights is strikingly familiar from the literature on sex and gender during the Cold War era.

Hull puts much emphasis on the influence of the churches, showing that the Protestant church was not as progressive as some historical accounts make us believe when it came to sexuality. The church was so important to the development of negative and positive sexual norms that Hull starts her account of “The Christian Church and Sexual Regulation” with the sentence: “In the beginning was the Church” (p. 10), mirroring Nipperdey’s assertions of the importance of Napoleon and Bismarck that had been opposed by Wehler’s remark that there was no revolution in the beginning of German history. Only in response to late-18th-century philosophical theories about women’s crucial function in civil society, namely that they elicit morality in men (ch. 8), could reforms of the civil and/or criminal codes pertaining to sexuality and gender relations be enacted, for example the decriminalization of consensual sexual acts in Bavaria, including homosexual acts, prostitution, and non-reproductive sex (ch. 9), or the prohibition into the paternity of an illegitimate child and thus the de facto decriminalization of fornication in Baden (ch. 10). Despite the alleged liberations, many of these measures underwrote the asymmetry between men and women, strengthened the institution of heterosexual marriage, and only abandoned the idea of the necessarily reproductive meaning of sexual activity, Hull concludes (ch. 11).

Catherine Gallagher and Thomas Laqueur’s edited volume The Making of the Modern Body is a more body-centered history of sex/gender making in the 19th century than Hull’s is for the preceding century. The contributors mostly treat France and Victorian England, but an assessment of syphilis in Russia as well as an analysis of Walter Benjamin’s thoughts on Baudelaire’s writings are also in stock. Laqueur and Londa Schiebinger show in their studies about 19th-century reproductive biology and 18th-century anatomy the extent to which scientific knowledge is malleable and can be made to fit political and social concerns of the time. Hull’s observation that women were considered unfit as citizens but predestined for reproduction, for example, is reiterated in Schiebinger’s assessment of the first drawings of female skeletons with wide hips and tiny skulls. Similarly, Laqueur’s illustration of the transition from the one-sex to the two-sex model is a male counterpart to the feminist strategy of employing difference in order to achieve equal rights. Mary Poovey’s chapter on “’Scenes of an Indelicate Character’” elucidates the ways in which women appeared not only to be unfit but even dangerous. Victorian English doctors were very hesitant to anesthetize women during childbirth, Poovey shows, since they were afraid that repressed female desires and unchastity may suddenly erupt from the disinhibited female individual—a clear acknowledgement of the actors’ knowledge that they were oppressing women, I would say.

Prostitution is another prominent topic in this volume, as the three final chapters of the volume show. Laura Engelstein, in her aforementioned contribution about how “Russian Doctors View Syphilis, Social Class, and Sexual Behavior, 1890–1905,” explains the extent to which prostitution was only seen as a problem of the cities, whereas the peasants were perceived as a group of moral purity hat did not need to be coerced but only educated by the state in order to perform the civil duties. Christine Buci-Glucksmann’s chapter on Benjamin and Baudelaire, also mentioned above, argues that the prostitute became “an allegory of modernity itself” (p. xv) as a human commodity. Alain Corbin’s contribution makes clear that ‘the prostitute’, besides her commodification and problematic character in urban life was first and foremost a woman on whose back the evils of society were tried to be contained, an observation that resonates very well with Jann Matlock’s Scenes of Seduction (not on this list).

Reforming the Moral Subject is an analysis of changing sexual values and sexual liberation movements in the German-speaking countries of the late 19th and early 20th century. The so-called ethics reform was brought about by (mostly Jewish and Protestant) intellectuals and activists associated with psychology, philosophy, sociology, law, pedagogy, and eugenics, who borrowed the latest arguments from Darwinism, materialism, and the rising field of sexology. The reform movement was directed against repressive sexual values and institutions that Hull has laid out so clearly and it succeeded in drawing up an “ethical” (Ethik) analytical framework and vocabulary that allowed the reformers to talk about sexual “morality” (Sittlichkeit) with all of its highly intimate concern and its ruthlessly politicized meanings in the public sphere. It is thus a continuation of Hunt’s deconstruction of the private/public divide, or the individual/social distinction and aims at “resurrect[ing] the instability of social categories in order to depict the productivity of that instability” in order to show how fruitfully this instability was seized by contemporary actors (p. 14).

This intellectual history continues the list of accounts of predominantly middle-class individuals’ discontent with sex and gender in central Europe (an exception here is ch. 6 on the rise of the social democrats and their surprising embrace of the ideas of the ethics reform—though not its label). Matysik’s primary source material comprises mostly published works. In the first of three parts, Matysik illuminates the ways in which ethics, as an analytical tool that can aid secular social change, made its way into the German-speaking intellectual realm, institutionalized in the German Society for Ethical Culture (ch. 1), and got associated with the question of sexual mores and the Catholic relict of the Doppelmoral, not least through Helene Stoecker’s work on female sexual liberation and her founding of the League for the Protection of Mothers (ch. 2). Controversies around the recently introduced Civil Code and its discrimination against women and children, already addressed by Allen, were crucial to the early concerns of activists like Stoecker.

In the main part of her work, Matysik traces the associations and controversies between the aforementioned ethics and sexual liberation societies (ch. 3) as well as the global reach of the ethics reform, that is, primary a racialization of the movement and its ideas during European imperialism (ch. 4)—a development not at all surprising when read alongside Wildenthal’s account of the pervasiveness of questions of sex/gender and sexuality in the colonial context. The increasingly close association between ethics reform and sexual liberation reflected and contributed to a pervasive contemporary notion that all moral judgements and debates inevitably have to draw on the question of sexuality, Matysik shows. This theme is unpacked in chapter 5, where Matysik traces the debates surrounding a 1909 proposal to include the “female homosexual” in the German Criminal Code, in addition to the “male homosexual,” a subject Europeans were more familiar with. The controversy supports Scott’s argument that feminists sometimes emphasized sex/gender differences and sometimes similarities to gain equality: some feminists welcomed the proposed paragraph since it would further equalize men and women according to the law. Matysik’s statement “that ethics reform as a critical phenomenon died under the weight of politics, or rather became conflated with politics,” during and after WWI (p. 252) makes us wonder whether social and intellectual movements or wars have more power to change women’s rights.

Scott Spector et al.’s edited volume After the History of Sexuality reassesses Foucault’s account of The History of Sexuality in German-speaking Europe from the Middle Ages to the 20th century. The contributors attempt to not only extend and correct Foucault’s view on the making and disciplining of sexuality; they particularly aim at ending Foucaultianism, which in the editors’ view has hindered fruitful complements to Foucault’s sometimes static definitions and questionable periodization.

The contributions of the volume are short and many (20 incl. the Postscript), most of them with significant historiographical foundations as well as strong analytical and theoretical frameworks. Ulinka Rublack suggests that the allegedly 19th-century view, so aptly described by Matysik, that sexual desire is inherently human and that the morality of a person is inextricably bound with their sexual behavior was in fact a distinct development of Lutheranism, which brought about a new embodied notion of personhood, the need for a morality that could not regained by confession, and, thus, the need for public regulations of sexual behavior (ch. 3). Sexuality was thus defined as a political entity two centuries before Foucault assumed it was (ch. 2).

Several contributions in this volume attend to lesbians, a topic touched upon by Roberts, but not unpacked in detail by any of the aforementioned scholars. We are presented with the view, for instance, that a history of homosexuality must attend to lesbianism, a topic that Foucault mostly avoided (ch. 1); more concretely, the reader learns about the ways in which new sexological theories enabled lesbians to phrase their own identity in imperial Germany (ch. 6), and the intimate connection of shame and pleasure in the rising outings of lesbian behavior and identities in the Weimar Republic (ch. 10).

Taking seriously Foucault’s view of power as a two-way process, Robert Beachy elucidates the ways in which the police in imperial Germany (Berlin’s Department of Blackmailers and Homosexuals) did not only surveil but also protect the gay community. Policing was thus not only oppression and control as Hull and Surkis suggest, but at the same time lowered the odds of being blackmailed (a topic very familiar from Cold War times) by homosexual prostitutes; effectively, this ‘surveillance’ helped the gay community to gain more visibility, institutionally, socially, as well as in the media (ch. 7). Julia Roos shows similar agency in female prostitutes during the Weimar Republic (ch. 9). Empowered by their recently gained suffrage, a newly formed union, and the public press, officially registered prostitutes protested against the criminalization of their profession, the closure of brothels, their social and legal marginalization, restrictions of residence and movement, as well as compulsory health checks and potential forced hospitalizations. They were partially successful in asserting authority over their work and bodies and changed the landscape of German policing of sexuality.


Book Summaries Cont’d: 20th-Century Sexuality and Sexology

$
0
0

The items below do a fantastic job in connecting the “private” with the “public” spheres—and show that they’re not actually separate spheres whatsoever. Many of these works, I already utilized during a research project on a statistical review of the Kinsey Report. I haven’t had time to revise the research paper that grew out of this project in order to get it accepted at a journal, but I’m positive that this will be easier as soon as I don’t have to read 13 books per week anymore. Just like the reading list on post-WWII US science and second-wave feminism, from which the following items are a part, I worked with Susan Lindee on this research paper.

Works Read

Sexological Surveys:

Ericksen, Julia A. and Sally A. Steffen. 1999. Kiss and Tell: Surveying Sex in the Twentieth Century. With the assistance of S. A. Steffen. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Robinson, Paul A. 1989. The Modernization of Sex: Havelock Ellis, Alfred Kinsey, William Masters and Virginia Johnson. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

Reumann, Miriam G. 2005. American Sexual Character: Sex, Gender, and National Identity in the Kinsey Reports. Berkeley: University of California Press.

(Non-)Heterosexuality:

Fausto-Sterling, Anne. 2000. Sexing the Body: Gender Politics and the Construction of Sexuality. New York: Basic Books.

Lewis, Carolyn H. 2010. Prescription for Heterosexuality: Sexual Citizenship in the Cold War Era. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press.

Block, Andreas de, and Pieter R. Adriaens. 2013. “Pathologizing Sexual Deviance: A History.” Journal of Sex Research 50 (3–4): 276–98. doi:10.1080/00224499.2012.738259 .

Meyerowitz, Joanne J. 2002. How Sex Changed: A History of Transsexuality in the United States. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Terry, Jennifer. 1999. An American Obsession: Science, Medicine, and Homosexuality in Modern Society. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Johnson, David K. 2004. The Lavender Scare: The Cold War Persecution of Gays and Lesbians in the Federal Government. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

D’Emilio, John. 1998 (1983). Sexual Politics, Sexual Communities: The Making of a Homosexual Minority in the United States, 1940–1970. 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Escoffier, Jeffrey. 1998. American Homo: Community and Perversity. Berkeley, Los Angeles: University of California Press.

Sociologist Julia Ericksen’s first monograph, Kiss and Tell, was researched and written in collaboration with lawyer (to be) Sally A. Steffen. The two authors draw on interviews as well as published popular and scientific literature in order to elucidate the social and political contexts of sexological surveys in the 20th-century US. The book progresses chronologically, but the chapters have thematic focuses reflecting major concerns of the time: from male to female to adolescent sexuality, to sex therapy and sex crime, to homosexuality and HIV/AIDS, with generally increasing political and media interest.

Ericksen and Steffen put much emphasis on the researchers’ goal to create ‘objective’ numbers about sexuality and to use these as a basis for typing sexual behavior and classify sexually active individuals (ch. 10). Even though the researchers believed that they were uncovering innate sexuality, the authors argue that these surveys have created sexuality and changed sexual behavior by suggesting to certain societal groups that they can, should, or should not behave as reported. The authors frame the development of sex surveys as “a history of the growing sophistication of researchers and the increasing certainty of their conclusions” (p. 10) and explain that “superior methods” (p. 7) were only slowly taken up by the researchers who, in particular in the first half of the 20th century, “did not understand … the importance” of appropriate sampling, the impact of the interview questions and the interviewer on the results gathered, or the problem of biased data analysis. The authors explain why this may have been the case: because researchers were oftentimes isolated since ‘sex talk’ was virtually impossible in any social realm.

In the early 20th century (and again during the Cold War), sexual behavior was closely linked with the moral character of a person. The hygiene movement in the early 20th century and the rise of the New Woman made it even more desirable for religious and political authorities to advocate for the restriction of sexual behavior to reproductive acts in heterosexual marriages, an attitude that was slowly abandoned during the first 30 decades of the 20th century. Ericksen and Steffen draw on Michel Foucault and use his concepts of sexuality as a tool to put forth their own agenda, namely that future sexology needs to self-reflexively study sexuality as something that is ‘made up’ by all the aforementioned factors and the presentation of sex surveys in the media.

Paul Robinson’s lucidly written intellectual history of The Modernization of Sex covers the work of “major sexual theorists” of the 20th century (p. 191): H. Havelock Ellis, Alfred Kinsey, as well as William Masters and Virginia Johnson, whom Robinson frequently compares to each other and to Sigmund Freud. In the three essays that make up his book, Robinson does not attend to any of the political and social developments Ericksen identifies as crucial for the research direction, funding, and reception of sexological surveys. He aims instead at illustrating the ideas of “sexual modernism as a reaction against Victorianism” (p. 191), that is, against the oppressive notion of the close link between moral character and sexual behavior. This lack of context leaves him unable to explain the alleged setbacks of liberation he identified in Master and Johnson’s work.

Even though Ericksen illustrates the Victorian concepts of guilt and immoral sexuality as late as during the HIV/AIDS epidemic, Robinson shows how theories about masturbation, female sexuality, sexual deviance, and non-reproductive intercourse indeed have episodically become less oppressive. The modernizer of sexuality according to Robinson, Ellis, had a Romantic approach to sex and devoted his research to the liberation of sexuality in the interest of sexual pleasure in affectionate monogamous heterosexual relationships with occasional additional affectionate affairs. This set the stage for Kinsey’s much more radical and “naturalistic” (p. 56) approach to sex. Kinsey also advocated for sexual liberation, but sought to divorce erotic encounters from emotional attachment. In this regard, Robinson suggests, Kinsey was entirely anti-Romantic.

Masters and Johnson returned to some of the Romantic ideas, for example, the close link between affection and sexuality. They exhibited a therapeutic approach to sex, including a critical stance towards homosexuality. Kinsey’s naturalism, however, was reflected in their “clinical” or “heartless” research methods (p. 195); instead of surveying, they directly manipulated intercourse in their lab and dissected the sexual response into four phases—an exemplar of their consistent imprecision, Robinson argues very entertainingly. In this connection, their framing of sexual intercourse as “work” resonates very well with Emily Martin’s metaphoric analysis of women’s reproductive labor.

Miriam Reumann’s first monograph, American Sexual Character, zooms in on Kinsey’s work and its reception in the US during the 1940s and 1950s “as a Rorschach test for postwar Americans” (p. 13). Reumann draws on scientific and popular periodicals, newspapers, cartoons, films, fiction, and advice literature as well as the archival collection at the Kinsey Institute in order to elucidate the ways in which Americanness, masculinity, femininity, marriage, family, and sexuality were bound together in the early Cold War. After a first chapter covering the bases of the post-war “sexual order” in the US, Reumann devotes one chapter to Kinsey’s male report, one to the female, one to the question of marriage and (pre)marital intercourse, and a last one to the question of homosexuality before a substantial epilogue closes the book with broader considerations of sexuality as an “orgone box” in the US, or, more specifically, its middle classes, during the early Cold War. This close link that social scientists and the public established between sexuality and citizens’ morality sounds very familiar by now. And as a sequel to Sarah Igo’s assertion that Americans identified themselves with surveys like Kinsey’s, Reumann argues that Americans of the 1950s “celebrated the idea of an essential American character” (p. 198).

The topics Reumann identifies in the controversial debates surrounding Kinsey’s publications resonate very well with James Gilbert’s depiction of factors contributing to a perceived masculinity crisis in the 1950s: the fear of the effeminate man with homosexual tendencies (chs. 2 and 5), the concerns about surprisingly unruly “average” women (ch. 3), the worries surrounding mass consumption and morally erosive popular culture (chs. 1 and 5), and the difficulties of adjusting to the new ideal of companionate nuclear families and the danger of uncontrollable demands for sexual fulfillment (ch. 4). Furthermore, Reumann illustrates that different groups, pro- and anti-governmental, used the Kinsey Reports for their own gains, interpreting the numbers as they saw fit. This malleability of Kinsey’s allegedly ‘hard data’ is striking. In my last essay, we have seen how Stephen Robertson’s and Marga Vicedo’s actors have reinterpreted the guilt of mothers (overprotection vs. deprivation) as the political demands were changing, but Reumann exemplifies how numbers can in the very same moment serve contradictory agendas.

Sexing the Body is biologist Anne Fausto-Sterling’s second monograph. With political vigor and autobiographical inspiration, Fausto-Sterling tackles the un-naturalness of “sex” by analyzing the scientific publications and practices surrounding three major instances of “sexing” in bio-medical practice and theory: intersex phenomena and involuntary surgical sex assignment as acts of anatomical, physiological, and psychological normalization (chs. 2–4), the translation of gender roles into alleged brain sex differences in the corpus callosum (ch. 5), and the un-linkable gender-steroid compound and the sexualization of so-called sex hormones (chs. 6–8). She provides numerous charts, tables, pictures, and cartoons in order to accentuate her argument that lots of labor is required to construct and uphold the concept of dichotomous sexes. Her argument proceeds in a somewhat Stephen-Gould-ian or Troy-Duster-ian manner. Despite (or because of?) its popular style, the book contains an extensive 217-page note and bibliography section, extending the already detailed discussion of scientific matters in the text even more and providing insight into Fausto-Sterling’s sources, predominantly published scientific texts from the late 20th century.

Many familiar ‘characters’ show up in this work. From Richardson’s “sex chromosomes” through John Money, who also plays a major part in Meyerowitz’s history of transsexuality (see below), to the gender-heterosexuality composite so popular during the Cold War. When Fausto-Sterling writes about “sex,” she addresses both meanings: “sex,” the complement to “gender,” and sexuality, for example, in the case of intersex individuals who have allegedly been assigned specific gender roles and sexual preferences together with their genitalia (ch. 3). Even though Fausto-Sterling references major theoretical texts, for instance, the works of Haraway, Foucault, Latour, and Hacking, she does not engage with such conceptual problems on a deeply theoretical level. In her final chapter, she reiterates her argument that nature and nurture cannot be distinguished, that the process of acquiring knowledge about humans is a social process, and that biology can never provide any ‘truth’ about sexuality. She advocates for interdisciplinary approaches to this sensitive topic, in teams including biologists as well as “feminist critical theorists” (p. 235). But how collaborations of this sort could be implemented remains an open question.

American women’s historian Carolyn Lewis’s first book, Prescription for Heterosexuality, assesses the “obsession” of Americans with heterosexuality in the post-war decades through the lens of physicians’ efforts to stabilize heterosexual lifestyles. Lewis’s main sources are popular advice literature as well as medical and scientific publications in periodicals and newspapers from the 1950s and 1960s, proceedings from professional conferences, as well as select archival collections. These sources allow Lewis to provide a fresh account of the aforementioned concerns surrounding premarital intercourse and teen pregnancies, increasing divorce rates and the pursuit of female sexual pleasure, as well as alternative masculinity, femininity, and marriage concepts. Lewis shows how the medical profession became crucial in the mediation and realization of governmental heteronormative policies. In doing so, she presents heteronormativity at the same time as one of several forms and as a foundation of all other forms of “domestic containment” in the face of nuclear threat (p. 5).

In chapters 2 and 4, Lewis shows how female sexual pleasure in “the home” was promoted in order to stabilize heterosexual marriages. Because the success of marital sexual relationships needed to be secured, doctors provided pre-marital sex instruction and monitored male and female reproductive health in mandatory pelvic examinations. Lewis also illustrates how general practitioners allied with psychoanalysts rather than psychiatrists, their professional competition, in combating female sexual dysfunctions; this offers an explanation for the sustained power of psychoanalysis in the late 20th century (see below). Lewis’s observation that women were blamed for their own and their husbands’ sexual dysfunctions (ch. 3) resonates well with Robertson’s and Vicedo’s accounts of mothers’ responsibility for societal degradation. And since the advent of artificial insemination (ch. 5), all biological reproductive responsibility was women’s. Men only had to make sure they and their wife lived an ideologically conform life so they could qualify for the procedure.

Philosophers Andreas de Block and Pieter Adriaens have compiled information from papers in biomedical, psychological, and historical online databases in order to provide a short account of 150 years of “Pathologizing Sexual Deviance” leading up to the publication of the DSM-V. The authors revisit Ellis, Freud, and Kinsey with a specific focus on their views on homosexuality. They trace the controversies surrounding the assessment of sexual deviances as “a disease” and “[a] biologically normal variant(s) of sexual variation” respectively (p. 277). De Block and Adriaens make clear that the interpretation of sexual deviance has always rested on ideological and political foundations: even though Freud did not consider homosexuality an illness, the powerful psychoanalysts of the American Psychological Association (APA) defined it as a symptom of an underlying psychopathology in the first two editions of the DSM. Only in the 1970s, when psychoanalysts lost their influence and psychiatrists rose to power within the APA, did the APA replace homosexuality that did not cause subjective distress with “sexual orientation disturbance” (p. 288). In the DSM-III and subsequent editions, the authors argue, “[t]he grand theorizing of … Freud has gradually been replaced by a more piecemeal, quantitative, and data-driven approach to sexual deviance” (p. 294), that is, by diagnostic criteria rather than etiological analyses. However, the question of why some fixations (heterosexual, homosexual) should be healthy while others are not (e.g., pedophilia, necrophilia), is still arbitrary, as the authors make very clear.

One of the alleged sex-linked psychopathologies covered by de Block and Adriaens is “transvestism,” a term that described trans-sex/gender phenomena when the first sex-reassignment cases became public in the 1930s. Joanne Meyerowitz’s second monograph, How Sex Changed, traces the histories of famous “transsexual” individuals (a term coined in 1949) as well as the public and scientific responses to these cases. Meyerowitz has worked extensively with contemporary popular press releases, scientific publications, and archival sources, in particular from highly visible trans* individuals like Christine Jorgensen, LGBTQ groups, and the Kinsey Institute.

Meyerowitz argues that the public and scientific engagement with trans* phenomena aided a rethinking of “sex” in the second half of the 20th century and stimulated the creation and acceptance of the “gender” concept (ch. 3); this process helped scientists, the broader public, and affected individuals to distinguish between or identify as “transsexuals,” “hermaphrodites,” and “homosexuals,” categories that had been enmeshed until the late 1950s (ch. 1). Over the course of the 1960s, legal and medical self-determination slowly increased for trans* individuals (ch. 4), but led also to a sexualization of MTF trans* conditions (ch. 5). The human rights movements of the 70s solidified the legally and medically beneficial developments (ch. 6), but also led to a clash with feminists, who disagreed with the MTF community’s celebration of femininity (ch. 7).

Meyerowitz’s argument that Jorgensen and other similar cases were fashioned with such a wide media coverage because post-war America was searching for new gender roles makes much sense in light of Gilbert’s, Vicedo’s, and Reumann’s works. Her claim that the notion of “sex” radically changed, however, and that this concept became less dichotomous and more malleable does align with the still ongoing pathologization of trans* phenomena in the DSM and in public perception as well as the trans* community’s petitions for equal treatment and more self-determination. Meyerowitz’s case studies are more cautious than these assertions in the introduction; they succeed admirably in illustrating the ways in which even radical figures like Jorgensen were to some extent still bound in traditional gender roles (e.g., in that she disapproved of women who supported their husbands financially; ch. 2). In providing an account of the disagreement between physicians and psychologists on whether to promote sex-reassignment surgery or preventive psychotherapy (ch. 3), the book also complements the history of the struggle for professional authority, which we have seen before in the social science / natural science competition, the psychiatrist / general practitioner rivalry, the “computer boys” / manager controversy, and the issue of military and government funding vs. academic independence.

Jennifer Terry’s third monograph, An American Obsession, focuses on the most pervasive form of sexual deviancy in the 20th century: homosexuality. “[W]hy homosexuality has been and continues to be demonized in the United States” is the puzzle she sets out to solve (p. 1). Terry’s book connects 18th-, 19th-, and 20th-century investigations into theories about the origins of homosexuality in Europe and the US (even though, as the title suggests, the focus is on the US) and thus also bridges my European History list (with Heidi) with these readings on US science.

Terry draws on a wide range of published medical, sexological, and social scientific texts, as well as on advocacy literature, legal cases, and archival sources—including, as so often, the Kinsey Institute archives. Informed by Foucault and feminist epistemologists, Terry illustrates the ways in which research into homosexuality has provided several governments and the public with the tools they needed to define normal sexuality and moral citizens. We have encountered this before, but Terry argues that the American concept of individuality combined with “the American cultural ethos of perfectionism and self-improvement” (p. 10) have shaped US homosexuality research and its uses in very particular ways, making exceptionally strong the connection between sexuality and morality, productivity, and class consciousness. Terry extends her view beyond sexuality and explains that homosexuals were construed as one in several groups of deviant citizens, sharing the outsider status with impoverished, political, and ethnic minorities, but that they nonetheless maintained some degree of agency (particularly well evidenced in homosexuals’ cooperation with the Committee for the Study of Sex Variants in New York City in the 1930s; chs. 6–8).

Terry’s account ties in many conceptual concerns and historical topics that already familiar from previously discussed works: the process of typing people like in Sorting Things Out (all chapters), the rise of the reproductive sciences as described by Reumann and Clarke (chs. 2, 3, 4), the power of psychoanalysis, which de Block and Adriaens have already identified in controversies surrounding the DSM (chs. 2, 9, 12), a fear of human degeneration in eugenic thought as explained in The Science of Human Perfection (ch. 3), the rise of sex surveys as described in Kiss and Tell (chs. 4, 6, 7, 9), the pervasiveness of endocrinology in matters of sex as shown in Sexing the Body and How Sex Changed (ch. 5), the sex crime panic of the early 20th century and concerns about masculinity in the early and mid-century as discussed by Robertson and Gilbert (chs. 5, 8, 10), the impact of Kinsey’s studies familiar from Igo’s, Clarke’s, Ericksen’s, Robinson’s, and Reumann’s works (chs. 9, 12), the rise in public family surveillance out of concern about ‘bad parenting’ as described by Vicedo (chs. 6, 10), the arising view of a more “fluid” sex since the 1930s as indicated by Meyerowitz (ch. 5), large-scale homophobic witch hunts during the Depression and in connection with anti-Communist measures akin to The Lavender Scare (see below; chs. 8, 11), and the rise of human rights movements, as discussed by Ericksen and D’Emilio (see below; ch. 12). This observation suggests that the history of gender and sexuality in the 20th-century US may actually be told through the history of homosexuality, broadly conceived.

The Lavender Scare is David Johnson’s first monograph; it aims at illustrating that the persecution of homosexuals was not a small-scale phenomenon in the periphery of the Red Scare but an extensive and deliberate political undertaking targeting sexual minorities during McCarthyism as well as under Eisenhower’s allegedly “more methodical, discreet, and just” security program (p. 146). Johnson draws on over two dozens of oral histories acquired by himself in the 1990s, court cases, popular press reports, and a large number of archival papers, including the collections of his main actors, gay rights organizations, and formerly classified documents from federal bodies. The picture he draws of the cruel persecutions from the late 1940s to the late 1960s captures both the political reasoning as well as the stories of affected individuals.

Johnson’s detailed history is set in Washington, D.C., as a formerly “gay city,” to which the homophobes turned most readily in their attempts to “clean” the government and public institutions of homosexuals, in particular at the State Department (chs. 2, 3), but the efforts extended even to international organizations (ch. 6). Sexual minorities were considered “perverts” (and thus likely to succumb to the ideology of communism as well) and easy targets of blackmail (and thus likely to be forced into pro-Soviet espionage), in short, they were “security risks” (chs. 1, 5).

Chapter 7 makes clear the fear that surveillance instilled in the gay community as well as different forms of resistance that grew out of it. Not informing or misinforming authorities in interrogations was one option that homosexuals chose; the rise of a gay press was another means of communicating and criticizing the discriminatory measures nation-wide. In addition, over the course of the 1950s, chapters of the Mattachine Society formed in different cities of the US; the one in D.C. called itself the Council for Repeal of Unjust Laws. Even though it did not have much direct success, Johnson’s sources allow him to convincingly argue that the roots of the gay rights movement lay in these instances of resistance (ch. 7, 8). The directed discrimination stimulated the radicalization of gay rights organizations as well as the solidarity amongst homosexuals whose social and legal victories created and rehabilitated “the homosexual citizen” (p. 214).

John D’Emilio’s first monograph, Sexual Politics, Sexual Communities, traces the formation of the “homophile movement” in the US from after WWII to after the Stonewall riots in 1969. D’Emilio’s sources are in large parts archival. Published diaries, (auto)biographies, oral histories, and gay periodicals also provide D’Emilio with significant information to help him answer the question of how allegedly isolated gay individuals could form a movement, including periodical publications and gay societies, while they were still in or just about to come out of ‘the closet’. D’Emilio’s periodization is roughly the same as Johnson’s, which makes apparent the shared argument that the gay liberation movement did not rise out of nothing in 1969. D’Emilio’s geographical scope is wider than Johnson’s and he focuses on the gay movements rather than on the persecution of gay individuals. The lens changes the narrative; for example, D’Emilio illuminates the ways in which the founders of the Mattachine Society managed to create safe spaces for militant activism aided by their experience of secrecy and hierarchy within the Communist party and how the second generation of leaders vehemently rejected these roots and sought broad social approval.

The reflections in the second edition of this book, 15 years after its first publication, are particularly interesting to read. D’Emilio mentions, for instance, that he researched the book during the 1979 riots in San Francisco, a much more violent form of activism than during the first 25 years after WWII. The book proceeds very effectively in order to argue that these years provided homosexuals with a “mixture of freedom [which stemmed from the social disruption of WWII as well as the sexual liberation] and oppression [which Johnson has elaborated upon so clearly]” (p. 252), which led to a geographically specific movement of politicized and self-identified gays and lesbians, laying the groundwork for the radical liberation from 1969 onwards. He also suggests that “those armed with … a willingness to engage in militant collective action,” initially along the east coast, were more effective in promoting change than their more peaceful fellows (p. 252).

Jeffrey Escoffier is a left and gay activist and writer; American Homo is a collection of eleven previously published essays (1985–1997), revised and framed by an introduction and conclusion. The essays are reactions to published works about homosexuals, about queer studies, and in queer, gay, and lesbian studies, as well as Escoffier’s own experience. Escoffier’s volume explores in three parts the rise of homosexual activism and liberation since the 1950s and the rise of gay/lesbian mainstreaming (Part I); the establishing of a public homosexual identity by lesbian and gay academic intellectuals, the institutionalization of gay and lesbian studies at American universities, starting in the 1970s, as well as the discourse-centrism of queer studies (Part II); and the challenges of competition between marginalized groups in the age of multiculturalism and the battle against the new Religious Right (Part III). These accounts are all remarkably autobiographical and driven by the conviction that, over the course of the 20th century, the US society has lost its “sociological imagination,” and that without it, people are unable “to navigate social change” (p. 15).

Escoffier suggests that institution-centrism and economization of lesbian/gay/queer studies and explanations of sexuality and other personal as well as intellectual characteristics as innate, rather than as social processes, have led to the contemporary “impoverished … idea of the social” (p. 15). With his account, Escoffier wants to offer queer studies and homosexual activism a mirror, a refreshing agenda in the face of often-times hostile critiques of the established academy like Fausto-Sterling’s. Even though the goals of this volume differ much from TallBear’s, the inclusion of autobiographical details is equally powerful in both accounts, and more substantially valuable than in Sexing the Body or in Fatal Invention, I would say.

Escoffier starts from the premise that “[h]omoeroticism pervades American life” (p. 4), an assertion that entails one of the public fears that led to the masculinity crisis as described by Gilbert. Escoffier provides an account of the stigmatization of ‘the homosexual’ in the 1950s and 1960s, with all of its economic, geographical (ch. 2), and identity-building consequences during the sexual revolution (chs. 1, 3). D’Emilio has elaborated on this topic in the context of the formation of homosexual organizations. This identification led to the normalization of ‘the homosexual’, Escoffier argues, and calls it “the politics of identity” (p. 34), a concept he juxtaposes with his argument for “the many ways of being homosexual” (p. 28). Finally, Escoffier advocates for a collaboration of lesbian/gay/queer activists with other social groups and also names a clear goal for the further intellectual development of the field: “Homo social theory must incorporate the larger historical structures of the economy, institutions, and the state in order to complement queer theory’s maps of discursive formations” (p. 184). This is a little bit more concrete than Fausto-Sterling’s wish, but still not very practicable.

Final Summaries on 20th-Century Science: Feminism and Science

$
0
0

The below essay was at the same time my favorite to write and my last one for my list with Susan Lindee. Concluding my readings in Cold-War Science and Feminism also brings me one step closer to my oral exams on May 6: this was the first one out of three lists that I completed reading. As of yesterday, I have finished all my lists (more essays to follow on this weblog soon).

I have some training in Gender Studies, most importantly through taking classes with Anelis Kaiser, Sabine Hark, and following the NeuroGenderings network, but taking time to (re)read and discuss the below works gave me a new perspective on my own work. I used to have problems calling myself a “feminist,” because I’ve seen a lot of unproductive deconstructivism in the public discourse. The below scholarship, however, together with my teachers and the NeuroGenderings network, offers a glimpse into the development towards productive feminist science critique that does not forget intersectionality—a scholarly project that I want to contribute to.

Works Read

History of Feminism:

Scott, Joan W. 1986. “Gender: A Useful Category of Historical Analysis.” American Historical Review 91 (5): 1053–75. doi:10.1086/ahr/91.5.1053 .

Rossiter, Margaret W. 1982. Women Scientists in America: Struggles and Strategies to 1940. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

Schiebinger, Londa. 1999. Has Feminism Changed Science? Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Creager, Angela N. H., Elizabeth Lunbeck, and Londa L. Schiebinger, eds. 2001. Feminism in Twentieth-Century Science, Technology, and Medicine. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. (Fedigan’s chapter is individually listed in section “Animals, Anthropomorphism, Sex, and Evolution.”)

 

Feminist Science Critiques:

MacCormack, Carol P., and Marilyn Strathern, eds. 1980. Nature, Culture and Gender. New York: Cambridge University Press.

Bleier, Ruth. 1984. Science and Gender: A Critique of Biology and Its Theories on Women. New York: Pergamon Press.

Keller, Evelyn F. 1985. Reflections on Gender and Science. New Haven: Yale University Press.

Hubbard, Ruth. 1990. The Politics of Women’s Biology. New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press.

Oudshoorn, Nelly. 1994. Beyond the Natural Body: An Archaeology of Sex Hormones. New York, London: Routledge.

van den Wijngaard, Marianne. 1997. Reinventing the Sexes: The Biomedical Construction of Femininity and Masculinity. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

Harding, Sandra G., and Jean F. O’Barr, eds. 1987. Sex and Scientific Inquiry. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Laslett, Barbara, Sally G. Kohlstedt, Helen Longino, and Evelynn Hammonds, eds. 1996. Gender and Scientific Authority. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Harding, Sandra G. 2006. Science and Social Inequality: Feminist and Postcolonial Issues. Urbana: University of Illinois Press.

In her seminal paper, Joan Scott argues that “Gender [Is] A Useful Category of Historical Analysis.” She reviews the ways in which the concept has been used by historians prior to the publication of her essay. Scott distinguishes between descriptive and more cause-related usages of the category. An example for the descriptive use is, in her eyes, women’s history within the contemporary historiographical paradigm. More radically, first, feminists have tried to seek the causes for patriarchy in gender binaries, thereby ignoring other forms of discrimination besides sexism, for instance, class and race. Second, scholars in a Marxist tradition have sought explanations for the evolvement of gender systems in modes of production, thereby reducing gender to a consequence of economic and class struggle. Third, Scott describes feminist psychoanalytical traditions for which Evelyn Fox Keller’s essays as well as Sandra Harding and Jean O’Barr’s edited volume (see below) provide examples. All of these works, Scott argues, do not allow historians to historicize gender as such and overcome the binary definition of this category. The gender concept Scott envisions comprises a social level of interpersonal relationships and perceptions of difference (1) as well as a more abstract level of power relationships (2). Within (1), the interplay between symbolic representations, normative ideas, institutional orders, and subjective identities can be assessed. (2) allows for an analysis of implicit exertions of power. A history that uses such a decisive gender concept, Scott suggests, refrains from reiterating historical notions of inequality, can ask new questions or rephrase old ones, is able to provide women with new historical agency, and could help imagining more egalitarian futures.

Historian of science Margaret Rossiter, well-known for her formulation of the “Matilda effect” (1993), provides an overview of the struggles of Women Scientists in America (and partially in Germany) with her monograph, which covers the years from the early 19th century through 1940, when a modern system of science with its disciplinary boundaries, associations, prizes, and funding structures was in place. Rossiter draws on a vast number of manuscript collections and oral histories from dozens of different archives, on published biographies, periodicals, and government reports, but also on statistical evidence and reference works for scientists. Combining numerical data with concrete case studies, Rossiter illustrates that, with few exceptions, male scientists actively hindered women’s access to equal education (chs. 1 and 2); to academic, government, industrial, and other employment (chs. 3–9); as well as to public and peer recognition (chs. 10 and 11).

Despite the fact that it was against the stereotypical idea of women (irrational, nurturing) to work in science (rational, technical), Rossiter shows that the 19th century with its growing scientific field offered unprecedented opportunities to both male and female scientists, as it was massively expanding and offering novel positions that could sometimes be filled with women. As the professionalization progressed in the late 19th century, job requirements were more specifically defined, leading to an exclusion of women. Women started pervading the scientific sphere in large numbers through clubs and museums in the late 19th century and gained the right to acquire Ph.D.s around 1900, as a consequence of feminist protests and claims for “fairness.” After that, however, women were contained in ‘feminine’ fields of science where they could use their “special skills” (e.g., “home economics” or child psychology) and/or they were prevented from getting jobs on top of the hierarchy, being stuck with low-payed observation or calculation tasks, for instance. They could not become full professors and were oftentimes excluded from professional societies; forming women scientists’ associations and advising newcomers to stick to the carved out niche fields were more a sign of resignation than of the success of the feminist science movement, Rossiter argues. The large numbers of women in science by 1940, she concludes, “had occurred at the price of accepting a pattern of segregated employment and underrecognition, which, try as they might, most women could not escape” (p. xviii). The exceptional few (e.g., Ruth Benedict and Margaret Mead, who studied under Franz Boas; cf. ch. 10) owed their recognition to male patrons.

Londa Schiebinger’s monograph Has Feminism Changed Science? explicitly engages with Rossiter’s work and is slightly more optimistic in its assessment of the effects of second-wave feminism on science than Rossiter’s analysis of the first wave. In three parts, Schiebinger investigates into the ways in which the growing number of women in science have shaped academic careers (Part I), disciplinary cultures (Part II), and the content of science (Part III). Schiebinger draws on recent publications on women and gender in science in order “to extract … a set of useful analytical tools” (p. 13) for further investigations into the topic and future support of gender equality in the scientific community, its methods, and its knowledge (pp. 186–190). She concludes that feminism has partly changed the number of women in the professions, research methods, and questions pursued, particularly in the human and biological sciences, but she also makes clear that there is much left to equalize, most notably when it comes to the mathematical and physical sciences or, more generally, the question of how to reconcile family and professional career as a woman.

This is not primarily a book written for historians of science. As Schiebinger explains in her introduction, it is “a translation project, an attempt to make clear to readers of diverse backgrounds and interests the important issues concerning the place of women and gender in science” (p. 2). This agenda of accessibility and broad appeal may be one reason for why Schiebinger does not offer substantial engagement with feminist epistemologies in this work. She focuses on the more practical questions of how women can enter and survive in scientific fields (the easier task) and how scientific research practices and topics can be less biased. Schiebinger’s desire for a diverse audience is also based on her insight that ‘feminism’ was not able to impose change on science from outside; to the contrary, feminists inside and outside of academia, non-feminist scientists, professional societies, university administrations, the government, and funding agencies need to be and have been involved in negotiations surrounding gender equality in science, not to mention cultural perceptions, public architecture, and classroom interaction from elementary school on.

Angela Creager et al.’s edited volume Feminism in Twentieth-Century Science is an extension of Schiebinger’s monograph offering different case studies that endorse Schiebinger’s argument that feminist changes of science (Part I), technology (Part II), and medicine (Part III) occurred as a movement from within various disciplines and were not in any way imposed on them from the outside. The range of contributions in Part I (archaeology, primatology, and biology) as well as the introduction echo Schiebinger’s assertion that the mathematical and physical sciences have not yet been transformed by feminist theories, values, and practices. In comparison with Part II, it becomes clear that what is presented as feminist influence on technology diverges from how feminism has reshaped science. Whereas the contributors to Part I argue that scientists, always seeking to approximate ‘the truth’ more closely, where (relatively) ready to adopt new questions, methods, and interpretations. In the realm of technology, however, feminism led to an acknowledgement of the importance of the (female) consumers besides the (male) producers and their product design.

In Part III, Nelly Oudshoorn and Evelynn Hammonds contribute analyses of the feminist fixation of studies on the female body and of the male-gay-centric HIV/AIDS debate respectively. Oudshoorn argues that feminist inquiries should henceforth include the male body in their analyses in order to develop, for instance, a male contraceptive. Overall, the contributions in Part III are more directed at the possibilities to invert sexual and gender stereotypes through and within medicine, not so much at the advance of scientific knowledge in gender-sensitive ways, or the redirection of technological production and the history of technology.

Carol MacCormack and Marilyn Strathern’s edited volume Nature, Culture and Gender comprises eight contributions, most of which are authored by female social anthropologists. The contributions build on and extend Sherry Ortner’s 1974 paper “Is Female to Male as Nature Is to Culture?,” in which Ortner identifies the widespread notion that women are closer to nature than men. The contributors to this volume assess in a more nuanced way the link between the female/male binary and the nature (or wild, animal) / culture (or tame, human) distinction in European cultures, arguing that it does not as such exist in non-‘Western’ societies.

In the second chapter, Maurice and Jean Bloch provide an analysis of 18th-century French definitions of “nature” and show how these often ambiguous notions were born out of social concerns or means of political critique. Subsequently, Ludmilla Jordanova complements the Blochs’ contribution with an inquiry into the scientific and social construction of “woman” in 18th-century Europe. She assesses contradictory scientific metaphors and symbols pertaining to the woman as scientifically explainable and yet dangerously passionate and argues that the male/culture versus female/nature opposition has been “mediat[ed by] science and medicine” (p. 45), because these fields allowed for the definition of women as “a distinct class of persons” (p. 47) and thus the naturalization of the social order and fashioned white men with a vocabulary for sex and gender discourses. The remaining chapters provide theorized anthropological studies of peoples in South America, Africa, and Oceania, illustrating that “alternative structures” (p. 21) of a world conceived in binaries including gender and nature/culture are possible; none of the presented case studies present a simple ‘Western’ equation of male = culture and female = nature.

The following books are amongst the earliest feminist science critiques. Bleier, a neuroanatomist, provides a consideration of “nature” constructs within the ‘biological peoples’ and thus extends MacCormack and Strathern’s volume. In her own words, “[t]his book is concerned with the role of science in the creation of an elaborate mythology of women’s biological inferiority as an explanation for their subordinate position in the cultures of Western civilizations” (p. vii). This argument is based on analyses of theories of Wilsonian sociobiology (ch. 2), neurobiology (ch. 3), neuroendocrinology (ch. 4), evolutionary biology (ch. 5), anthropology (ch. 6), and medico-scientific discourses of human sexuality (ch. 7). Pointing to flawed methodologies, inconclusive findings, and proposed alternative theories, Bleier argues that the scientific claim of discovering nature and objectively explaining it is but a strategy to conceal a political endeavor.

Bleier’s goal is not to work out strategies for how scientific authority could be attained after all; in line with later arguments by Sandra Harding, for instance (see below), she argues for an abandonment of the objectivity illusion and an acknowledgement of the fact that all scientific knowledge is made by subjective subjects, and not a neutral read of some independently existing entity we can call ‘nature’. In a final chapter, she proposes “a feminist science that begins by discarding dualistic assumptions as well as concepts of control and dominance and of linear causality” (p. ix). Such a science would abandon all notions of biological determinism and instead be characterized by an “understanding of the constant change, complexity, contextuality, and interaction that characterize natural and social phenomena and our lives” (p. ix). As Harding argued a few years later, this is a call for another form of ideological science, but one that is, more reflexive and thus, so the hope, “better and more humane” (p. 207) than the standard in the 1980s.

Evelyn Fox Keller, a mathematical biophysicist by training, also addresses the political nature of scientific truth claims. Her volume Reflections on Gender and Science consists of nine essays, some of which are revised versions of papers published in the 1970s and 1980s. She succeeds exceptionally well in the synthesis of the diverse chapters, not least because each of the three parts of the book is fashioned with its own introduction, in addition to the overall introduction and a programmatic epilogue. Keller assesses science and gender by means of historical (Part I), psychoanalytical (Part II), and scientific/philosophical analyses (Part III). More specifically, she argues in chapters 2 and 3 that scientists before and during the Scientific Revolution painstakingly negotiated a scientific style and a notion of gender dichotomy that stuck with us, namely “an objectivist ideology, prematurely proclaiming anonymity, disinterest, and impersonality and radically excluding the subject” (p. 12), which was, additionally, laden with sexual metaphors and ideas of domination. In other words, science was masculinized more about four centuries ago.

Chapters 4 through 6 examine this specific scientific style and its naturalization psychoanalytically, after a well-reflected justification for doing so. The appropriation of psychoanalysis is rather widespread in second-wave feminism, as Harding and O’Barr’s edited volume shows (see below). In these chapters, Keller champions the unconscious longing for personal autonomy and the interpersonal project of domination (of ‘nature’ or women) as the basis for scientists’ claims of objectivity, that is, their assertion to be able to divorce the object of study from themselves as subjects, a developmental achievement according to Freudian psychoanalysis. The final three chapters are more concrete case studies in quantum mechanics and genetics; they illustrate that science cannot or does not exclusively proceed in the unified ‘masculine’ manner exposed in chapters 1 through 6; nonetheless, the idea of science as a field of competition and dominance is upheld by scientists themselves and in society more broadly.

Trained biologist Ruth Hubbard’s monograph, The Politics of Women’s Biology, reaffirms aforementioned claims that “science is no more immune from ideological commitments than are other human activities” (p. 211) and, in particular, that “biology is profoundly political” (p. 209). Only exposing the political nature of science, Hubbard argues, will legitimize feminists’ political demands to democratize the scientific field, its mechanisms, and its products. Like Scott, Hubbard is attentive to inequalities based on class and race (and ableness), and like Keller and Harding (see below), she propositions a different version of science, honoring the benefits of scientific pursuit per se.

Parts of the content of this book were previously published in the 1970s and 1980s and the chapters differ significantly in length and the form of evidence that is drawn on. What makes this volume nonetheless feel coherent is that it is written in an opinionated tone throughout and void of any footnotes or chapter-specific references besides the bibliography at the end of the book. This is thus more of a think piece than a history of gender in biology. Drawing on scientific episodes from the 19th and 20th centuries as well as on fictional portrayals of related issues, Hubbard attends to the ways in which biologists create knowledge and how women figure in this process (Part I); what the content of this knowledge is in genetics, evolutionary biology, and sociobiology (Part II); and to what ends this knowledge is used and what value statements these applications (re)produce in the field of reproductive technologies, which are mainly accessible to affluent, healthy, well-educated, heteronormative white families (Part III).

Dutch STS scholar Nelly Oudshoorn’s Beyond the Natural Body is “an archaeology of sex hormones” from the early years of European endocrinology in the 1920s and 1930s to the arrival of the birth control pill on the market in the 1960s in the US. This study is more in-depth than the previously discussed feminist accounts and less polemical than many of these. Oudshoorn emphasizes the Dutch part of the ‘sex hormone’ history, not least because the Netherlands were at the forefront of endocrinology research, partially under Thomas Laqueur’s uncle Ernst. Oudshoorn draws on published scientific material, feminist science critiques, STS, and histories of science, for instance, Adele Clarke’s work on reproductive science. She provides a critical assessment of the ways in which hormones were made scientifically accessible, sexed, gendered, as well as how they helped define new uses for existing healthcare facilities (the “resource network”; p. 141) and made possible the medicalization of hitherto ‘healthy’ states of the female body.

A novelty in Oudshoorn’s book as compared to similar accounts discussed here is that the present analysis goes beyond the laboratory and clinical practice and also looks at “pharmaceutical entrepreneurs” (p. 10) who harnessed and shaped the new knowledge starting in the 1930s (ch. 5). Furthermore, Oudshoorn draws on Ludwik Fleck’s concept of “prescientific ideas,” a notion that allows her to illustrate that “sex hormones” were not born of nothing, but that the theory formed slowly, out of an ambiguous idea of physical sex differences located in the ovaries and testes (ch. 2). This redefinition led to “a chemical model of sex and the body” (p. 144), culminating in a removal of the notion of “sex” from the uterus or the gonads and transforming it into an entity that permeates the entire body. The new understanding also turned the body into a potential site of experiments (chs. 3 and 6). At the same time, female bodies were re-defined as ‘cyclically sexed’, as the hormones wax and wane with the menstrual cycle, an observation that led to an ever more increasing reproductive view of women, the consequences of which are so aptly described in Emily Martin’s The Woman in the Body. Throughout the book, Oudshoorn makes very clear that holding on to the two-sex model was an arbitrary decision since from the early 20th century on, researchers found that “sex hormones” of both “sexes” appear in males and females, an observation that already led Fausto-Sterling to insist on a multiple-sex model.

Biologist Marianne van den Wijngaard’s monograph Reinventing the Sexes starts where Oudshoorn stops: after sex hormones have been established. This book is an analysis of the ways in which neuroendocrinology has redefined ‘sex’ since the 1980s. It traces and continues the critique of an alleged nature/nurture divide that was socially established and supported scientifically by organization theory, a Cold War theory about the neuroendocrinological bases of sex, gender identity, and behavior. As van den Wijngaard argues, the redefinition of ‘sex’ happened in response to feminist critiques and the increasing influx of women into the sciences since the 1970s. Van den Wijngaard bases her argument mostly on the discussion of published biological and social science literature, giving preference to female and/or feminist authors.

For the first decade since its inception in 1959, van den Wijngaard shows, brain organization research proceeded virtually unchallenged. But starting in 1971, the advent of second-wave feminism questioned these ideas and led to a gradual reconfiguration of the sex and gender definitions within science; methods were refined, resulting in the abandonment of a one-sex model in favor of a more independent view of the sexes. Van den Wijngaard’s major concern is not to debunk brain organization theory, as, for instance, Rebecca Jordan-Young does in Brain Storm (on my list for John), but to illuminate the extent to which feminism has made a difference in the understandings of “male” and “female” as well as “masculinity” and “femininity” in the network of biomedical sciences, psychology, and psychiatry until 1985, resonating with Schiebinger’s monograph and Creager’s edited volume.

Sex and Scientific Inquiry is a collection of essays previously published in Signs between 1975 and 1987. Philosopher Sandra Harding and political scientist Jean O’Barr edited the volume, which comprises fifteen feminist essays pointing to gendered elements in “The Social Structure of Science” (Part I), “Misuses and Abuses of Science and Technology” that benefit the stabilization of sexist and racist social orders (Part II), sex-difference “Bias in the Sciences” (Part III), “Sexual Meanings of Science” (Part IV), and, finally, reflections on feminist “Epistemology and Metatheory” (Part V). The contributions are very diverse in their length, methodology, disciplinary style, and period covered, from annotated pictures (ch. 3) through research articles in 17th-century alchemy (ch. 5), long historiographical surveys in women’s history of technology (ch. 4), analyses of the policy impact of ‘bad’ genetic science (ch. 6), and biological explanations of the variability in sex differences across populations (ch. 7) to philosophical assessments of the contradictions within feminist science critique, namely that feminist ideas are just as biased as contemporary scientific practice (ch. 15). Despite the wide variety covered, the biological and psy-sciences are the focus of this volume.

Many of the contributions, in particular in the latter half of the volume, revert to Freudian psychoanalysis in their analyses. Patricia Y. Miller and Martha R. Fowlkes, for example, provide an entertaining reading of the works of several sex researchers, concluding that S. Freud’s andro- and hetero-centrism permeate the work of Kinsey, who encouraged females to engage in premarital intercourse in order to satisfy male sexual needs, and the writings of Masters and Johnson, who described the vagina as a tool for heterosexual reproductive intercourse that can best function in the context of a healthy marriage (ch. 8). Evelyn Fox Keller (ch. 12) concludes her psychoanalytic study of the emphasis on objectivity, autonomy, dominance, and power in science “as an oedipal project” (p. 243) with the assertion that science is not per se bad and that feminists can change it, a notion very similar to Helen Longino and Ruth Doell’s assessment of the feminist qualms and hopes surrounding the biases towards sex differences and female inferiority in evolutionary biology and endocrinology (ch. 9).

Barbara Laslett et al.’s edited volume Gender and Scientific Authority is the sequel to Sex and Scientific Inquiry, comprising fifteen papers published in Signs in the 1980s and 1990s. In the editors’ words, it is “a continuation and a revision of the perspectives” in the 1987 volume (p. 1). In the 1996 volume, “sex” is replaced by “gender” as an analytical category, “science” is defined more broadly, including medicine and the social sciences, and race as well as non-‘Western’ cultures get a little bit more airtime. The papers, organized in four parts, are methodologically diverse; most of them discuss gender in a manner that is rather anthropological, philosophical, or sociological than deeply historical—seemingly a characteristic shared by feminist science critiques despite Scott’s conviction that thorough history using gender as an analytical category could advance science and societal structures. Exceptions to this trend are some of the chronologically organized historical studies in Part II, which deal with episodes of the exclusion of women from the 19th and 20th centuries sciences.

Part I addresses critiques of standpoint theory, for instance, by means of elaborating on the irreducible uniqueness of “Black Feminist Thought,” resulting from the experience of “add[ed] layers of oppression” (p. 31; ch. 1), and by suggesting epistemological adjustments through which standpoint theory can be saved from slipping into relativism that would forbid any political action (ch. 3). Part III focuses on the ‘scientific’ construction of sex differences in the realm of the social and psy-sciences. These case studies exemplify “the intersection of the social and the scientific” (p. 9), for instance, in the overlap between lesbian accounts, journalistic sensationalism, and sexological definitions of the female homosexual in the US around 1900 (ch. 8) or the observation that M. Charcot visually diagnosed his lower-class patients while S. Freud preferred to listen to his privileged clientele (ch. 9). Finally, Part IV attends to more contemporary instances of gendered scientific discourse. Most famously, Emily Martin’s paper “The Egg and the Sperm” (ch. 12) is part of this chapter. Other contributions look at the gendering of intersex infants (ch. 13), the use of primatology as a determinant of ‘natural’ development (ch. 14), and the influence of state reproductive policies on the private procreational life of individuals in China (ch. 15).

Science and Social Inequality is a collection of papers written and revised by Sandra Harding; earlier versions of the chapters were published or presented in public in the 1990s and early 2000s. The essays provide an overview of Harding’s endorsement of the standpoint theory (particularly ch. 5) and the past achievements of “heterogeneous” feminisms (p. 68); with this collection, Harding aims at stimulating a debate on “how better to harness modern Western sciences for social justice projects” (p. ix).

Harding starts off Part I, “The Social World of Scientific Research,” by justifying feminist and postcolonial science studies with the argument that it is unconceivable that so-called Western science was not constructed in a way that it served white imperial supremacy (ch. 1). The following chapters lay out the specific problems of science that Harding wishes to combat. First, the restriction of judgement of the truth of scientific theories—and of the paradigms more broadly—to a circle of initiated members of the community (ch. 2). This point connects closely to the dismissal of other traditions of knowledge (ch. 3). Second, scientists’ refusal to take responsibility for any harm that is done on physical, social, political, or epistemological levels as soon as their science leaves the site of research (ch. 2). Third, the denial of specific “sociologies, ethnographies, political economies, and histories” (p. 80), which she sees systemically intertwined with the ‘nature’ that the ‘natural’ sciences investigate into (ch. 4)—even in “good science” (p. 80), not only in the flawed science of a few misogynists, racists, classists, etc. (ch. 5). She mentions, for instance, “discriminatory social structures” in scientific institutions (p. 69), “sexism and androcentrism in the results of research” (p. 72), as well as anti-democratic ways of teaching science and technology. Fourth, the subjugation of the environment and ‘the West’s’ neighbors in the form of pollution, exhaustion, and colonialization (ch. 6).

Three chapters in Part II define the “political unconscious of modern Northern sciences” (p. 115) as a contradictory mix of democratic and anti-democratic values within both the practice of science and contemporary philosophy of science. Very concretely, Harding argues that “all sciences must be ‘ethnosciences’” (p. 140) and abandon “truth claims, which are “dysfunctional” (p. 133), in order to gain a more objective view of the world. In her final chapter, Harding explains why accepting the premise that the ‘Western’ system of knowledge does not have ‘the truth’ does not necessarily lead to a “damaging [epistemological] relativism” (p. 146) that leaves us without any tools to assess the aptness of a hypothesis, a concern also uttered in Gender and Scientific Authority. Rather, Harding suggests to work towards a multiplicity of sciences and philosophies of science that humbly provide the best possible interpretations of the world within a specific social and cultural network of individuals (ch. 9).

“I’m Not a Bigot, It’s Just Science”

$
0
0

You have probably already heard of Grace Pokela’s pointed facebook post that dismantles the “science” of transphobia. But just in case you haven’t—and chances are you haven’t, because I myself only learned about it through my brother—you should totally check it out.

It’s important to remind ourselves that “science” can be used quite easily to essentialize socio-economic injustice and culturally specific stereotypes. But it’s not only the misrepresentation of scientific “facts” that is the problem (e.g., denying that there’s more than XX and XY). Sometimes it is the bare attempt of scientifically classifying individuals that is already problematic. Typing humans secures the basis for discrimination, regardless of how fine-grained the categories are.

And I’m not only talking about sex/gender. My dissertation traces the 150-year-old obsession with the classification and etiology of handedness (yes, left- or right-hand preference). We find the same awful story here that we have witnessed—and continue to witness—for classifications of sex/gender, sexual orientation, race, and intelligence: fine and finer measures, and theories of the allegedly innate roots of these characteristics that oscillate between anatomy, genetics, and endocrinology.

Just like there is no “male” or “female,” there is no “left-handed” or “right-handed.” Lucky me, researchers since Broca have regarded handedness an unpolitical topic, so they were not very guarded in their publications about the topic. Stereotypes in my sources abound, and “the” left-hander is frequently associated with things inferior and deviant.

The history of handedness research is sexed/gendered, sexualized, racialized, class-ized, able-ized, and you-name-it-ized. It’s a very sad story. But one from which we can learn a lot. Stay tuned.

Must Read: Article in The CUT on Science and Sexual Stereotyping

$
0
0

When I was still sleeping this morning, Melinda Wenner Moyer published a spot-on article in The CUT, “These Ideas About Sexual Attraction May Be Based on Shoddy Science.” Moyer traced the controversy around French psychologist Nicolas Guéguen’s questionable research on social interactions between men and women. She did an excellent job at connecting evolutionary biologists’ tendency to sexual stereotyping with the current conversation around sexual harassment and other forms of sexualized violence. You should definitely read for yourself, but here’s a little teaser:

We are finally, as a country, publicly acknowledging that men have been treating women like shit for ages. Now, even the science that lends support to our iconic gender stereotypes—the science that reinforces the idea that men are biologically programmed to be sex-crazed and that women are basically sex objects—is coming crashing down, too.

Let’s hope that Moyer is right. I’m less optimistic that patriarchy and sexism are crashing down just yet.

Many thanks to Jonathan D. Moreno (quoted in the article) for drawing my attention to this piece.

Viewing all 19 articles
Browse latest View live




Latest Images